The book in...
One sentence:
A long and dry, but interesting, walk down the ages, taking in the progress of philosophy from the ancient world to the modern world, with a layover in the Catholic philosophy connecting them.
Five sentences:
The book is divided into three main sections. First the early ancient philosophy gives way to the middle Catholic philosophy, which acts as a connection to, lastly, modern philosophy. These three sections cover an enormous amount of history, but usually only scratches the surface. Each chapter, which briefly covers what could and is be a book in its own right, looks, usually, at a single philosopher. Overall I think the book is useful for not only its overview of the history of western philosophy, but as a look into Russell's thought process.
designates my notes. / designates important.
Thoughts
This book covers a lot of ground, but, while it is over 800 pages, it couldn’t
possible go into any great detail. It is divided into three main sections:
Ancient, Catholic, and Modern.
My main reason for reading this was to get a look into Bertrand Russell’s mind,
to see how he sees. I was not let down, for there are numerous occasions where
Russell puts forth his personal thoughts and feelings toward a particular
subject.
Overall I’d say it was very approachable and possibly a nice primer for one
interested in pursuing a more detailed examination of philosophy.
I read, on the internet, that there are a lot of errors within this book. Not
being intimately familiar with most of what is covered the errors, if there are
any, were unclear to me.
Most interesting to me was the Catholic portion of the book. The ancient view
is often placed on a pedestal today, a pining for the good old days when
Aristotle had figured everything out - from the gait of animals to the
celestial spheres. Likewise, the modern is also lauded. How many people today
praise Nietzsche and Kant, Hobbes or Rousseau? But the Catholic contributions
are often excluded from the accolades. This is probably due to the
anti-religious climate we live in, but it is, none-the-less, extremely
interesting and important in linking the ancient and modern eras.
I am not going to attempt any great synopsis of this book, though, if you are
interested in philosophy or Bertrand Russell, I can suggest it as worthwhile.
Instead I will offer up a few “hmmm” passages that stuck out to me.
The first “illustrates the connections of the Sophists with the law-courts”:
There is a story about Protagoras, no doubt apocryphal, which illustrates the
connection of the Sophists with the law-courts in the popular mind. It is said
that he taught a young man on the terms that he should be paid his fee if the
young man won his first law-suit, but not otherwise, and that the young man’s
first law-suit was one brought by Protagoras for recovery of his fee.
There is no further examination of the sophist philosophy being one of victory,
no mention of clever, but not necessarily factual, arguments, which should be
better called fallacies, being employed to win the case. Exactly what we see in
the modern court system, which has no use for truth in lieu of a compelling
argument. Crudely, it reminds me of the old Edgar Snyder advertisement (how
effective was it I still remember it after a decade since last seeing it?)
where he states, “there’s no fee unless we get money for you!”
Next is nothing but pure speculation on my part. Interesting to consider, but
it proves nothing.
Athens had lagged behind many other Greek cities; neither in art nor in
literature had it produced any great man (except Solon, who was primarily a
lawgiver).
I was immediately reminded of Fomenko’s work and drawn to compare Solon to
Solomon, both lawgivers.
Lastly, I found it extremely interesting, and quite a bit telling, that the
Piltdown man is used as an example. This hoax was used for such a long time
that, even if it is fake, the damage it caused, the belief in it so solid, that
generations of people have been misled. While the hoax is no longer fooling
anyone (if they even know what it is), the foundation it laid in support of
the Darwinian evolution theory is most certainly gospel among many still today.
One wonders what would have come of the theory had hoaxes like this not lent it
credibility.
Further, is it a coincidence that Bertrand Russell ran in the same circles as
Aldous Huxley, who’s Brave New World is based off of Russell’s Scientific Outlook. Is it
coincidence that Teilhard de Chardin’s hoax was promoted by Darwin’s bulldog,
none other than T.H. Huxley, grandfather to Aldous? The oligarchical
fingerprints act like breadcrumbs, back to the same self-proclaimed elite over
and over again.
The book concludes with a succinct consideration:
Philosophy, throughout its history, has consisted of two parts inharmoniously
blended: on the one hand a theory as to the nature of the world, on the other
an ethical or political doctrine as to the best way of living. The failure to
separate these two with sufficient clarity has been a source of much confused
thinking.
Further Reading
-
Saint Thomas Aquinas’s Summa contra Gentiles
-
Machiavelli’s the Discourses and The Prince (Those who do not read also the
Discourses are likely to get a very one-sided view of his doctrine.)
-
More’s Utopia (1518). (Utopia is an island in the southern hemisphere, where
everything is done in the best possible way.)
-
Hobbe’s Leviathan
-
Descartes’s Discourse on Method (1637) and the Meditations (1642)
-
Spinoza’s Ethics
-
Locke’s Essay on the Human Understanding and Patriarcha: or The Natural Power
of Kings
-
Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature
-
Rousseau’s The Social Contract and Emile
-
Kant’s The Critique of Pure Reason and Metaphysic of Morals (1785)
-
Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, Thus Spake Zarathustra, and Will to Power
-
John Dewey’s The School and Society (1899)
Exceptional Excerpts
Every community is exposed to two opposite dangers:
ossification through too much discipline and reverence for tradition, on the
one hand; on the other hand, dissolution, or subjection to foreign conquest,
through the growth of an individualism and personal independence that makes
co-operation impossible. In general, important civilizations start
with a rigid and superstitious system, gradually relaxed, and leading, at a
certain stage, to a period of brilliant genius, while the good of the old
tradition remains and the evil inherent in its dissolution has not yet
developed
It
might seem that the empirical philosopher is the slave of his material, but
that the pure mathematician, like the musician, is a free creator of his
world of ordered beauty.
Geometry, as
established by the Greeks, starts with axioms which are (or are deemed to be)
self-evident, and proceeds, by deductive reasoning, to arrive at theorems
that are very far from self-evident. The axioms and theorems are held to be
true of actual space, which is something given in experience. It thus
appeared to be possible to discover things about the actual world by first
noticing what is self-evident and then using deduction. This view influenced
Plato and Kant, and most of the intermediate philosophers. When the Declaration of Independence says “we hold these
truths to be self evident,” it is modelling itself on Euclid. The
eighteenth-century doctrine of natural rights is a search for Euclidean
axioms in politics.
“Self-evident” was
substituted by Franklin for Jefferson’s “sacred and undeniable."
Personal religion is derived from ecstasy, theology from
mathematics; and both are to be found in Pythagoras.
In studying a philosopher, the right attitude is neither
reverence nor contempt, but first a kind of hypothetical sympathy, until it
is possible to know what it feels like to believe in his theories, and only
then a revival of the critical attitude, which should resemble, as far as
possible, the state of mind of a person abandoning opinions which he has
hitherto held. Contempt interferes with the first part of this process, and
reverence with the second. Two things are to be remembered: that a man
whose opinions and theories are worth studying may be presumed to have had
some intelligence, but that no man is likely to have arrived at complete and
final truth on any subject whatever. When an intelligent man expresses a
view which seems to us obviously absurd, we should not attempt to prove that
it is somehow true, but we should try to understand how it ever came to seem
true.
The
doctrine that everything is in a state of flux is the most famous of the
opinions of Heraclitus, and the one most emphasised by his disciples,
as described in Plato Theaetetus.
The doctrine of Parmenides
was set forth in a poem On Nature. He considered the
senses deceptive, and condemned the multitude of sensible things as mere
illusion. The only true being is “the One,” which is infinite and
indivisible.
Athenian democracy, though
it had the grave limitation of not including slaves or women, was in some respects more democratic than any modern system.
Judges and most executive officers were chosen by lot, and served for short
periods; they were thus average citizens, like our jurymen, with the
prejudices and lack of professionalism characteristic of average
citizens. In general, there were a large number of judges to hear each
case. The plaintiff and defendant, or prosecutor and accused, appeared in
person, not through professional lawyers. Naturally, success or failure
depended largely on oratorical skill in appealing to popular prejudices.
Although a man had to deliver his own speech, he could hire an expert to
write the speech for him, or, as many preferred, he could pay for instruction
in the arts required for success in the law courts. These arts the Sophists
were supposed to teach.
The
disbelief in objective truth makes the majority, for practical purposes, the
arbiters as to what to believe.
He [Socrates] would ask such questions as: “If I wanted a shoe mended, whom should I employ?” To which
some ingenuous youth would answer: “A shoemaker, O Socrates.” He would go on
to carpenters, coppersmiths, etc., and finally ask some such question as “who
should mend the Ship of State?"
The
close connection between virtue and knowledge is characteristic of Socrates
and Plato. To some degree, it exists in all Greek thought, as opposed to that
of Christianity. In Christian ethics, a pure heart is the essential, and is
at least as likely to be found among the ignorant as among the
learned.
As
for economics: Plato proposes a thoroughgoing communism for the
guardians … The guardians are to have small houses and simple food; they
are to live as in a camp, dining together in companies; they are to have no
private property beyond what is absolutely necessary. Gold and silver are to
be forbidden. Though not rich, there is no reason why they should not be
happy; but the purpose of the city is the good of the whole, not the
happiness of one class. Both wealth and poverty are harmful, and in Plato’s
city neither will exist.
With feigned unwillingness,
the Platonic Socrates proceeds to apply his communism
to the family. Friends, he says, should have all things in common, including
women and children. He admits that this presents difficulties, but
thinks them not insuperable. First of all, girls are to have exactly the same
education as boys, learning music, gymnastics, and the art of war along with
the boys. Women are to have complete equality with
men in all respects.
“These
women shall be, without exception, the common wives of these men, and no one
shall have a wife of his own."
At certain festivals, brides and bridegrooms, in such numbers as are required to
keep the population constant, will be brought together, by lot, as they will
be taught to believe; but in fact the rulers of the city will manipulate the
lots on eugenic principles.
All children will be taken away from their parents at
birth, and great care will be taken that no parents shall know who are their
children, and no children shall know who are their parents.
intercourse is to be free, but abortion or infanticide is
to be compulsory.
Lying, Plato says explicitly, is to be a prerogative of the
government, just as giving medicine is of physicians.
On questions of fact, we
can appeal to science and scientific methods of observation; but on ultimate
questions of ethics there seems to be nothing analogous. Yet, if this is
really the case, ethical disputes resolve themselves
into contests for power– including propaganda power.
Thrasymachus proclaims
emphatically that “justice is nothing else than the
interest of the stronger."
We saw that God made only one bed, and it would be natural
to suppose that he made only one straight line. But if there is a heavenly
triangle, he must have made at least three straight lines. The objects
of geometry, though ideal, must exist in many examples; we need the
possibility of two intersecting circles, and so on.
Plato proceeds to an interesting
sketch of the education proper to a young man who is to be a guardian. We saw
that the young man is selected for this honour on the ground of a combination
of intellectual and moral qualities: he must be just and gentle, fond of
learning, with a good memory and a harmonious mind. The young man who has
been chosen for these merits will spend the years
from twenty to thirty on the four Pythagorean studies: arithmetic, geometry
(plane and solid), astronomy, and harmony.
What the above argument
amounts to is that, whatever else may be in perpetual flux, the meanings of words must be fixed, at least for a time,
since otherwise no assertion is definite, and no assertion is true rather
than false. There must be something more or less constant, if discourse and
knowledge are to be possible.
unless words, to some extent, had fixed meanings, discourse
would be impossible. Here again, however, it is easy to be too
absolute. Words do change their meanings; take, for example, the word “idea.”
It is only by a considerable process of education that we learn to give to
this word something like the meaning which Plato gave to it. It is necessary
that the changes in the meanings of words should be slower than the changes
that the words describe; but it is not necessary that there should be no
changes in the meanings of words
It will be seen that this
doctrine is optimistic and teleological: the universe
and everything in it is developing towards something continually better than
what went before.
The
world is continually evolving towards a greater degree of form, and thus
becoming progressively more like God. But the process cannot be completed,
because matter cannot be wholly eliminated. This is a religion of progress
and evolution…
The natural way to get
wealth is by skilful management of house and land. To the wealth that can be
made in this way there is a limit, but to what can be made by trade there is
none. Trade has to do with money, but wealth is not the acquisition of coin.
Wealth derived from trade is justly hated, because it
is unnatural. “The most hated sort, and with the greatest reason, is usury,
which makes a gain out of money itself, and not from the natural object of
it. For money was intended to be used in exchange, but not to increase at
interest. . . . Of all modes of getting wealth this is the most
unnatural”
I wrote an essay
once, called “Architecture and the Social System,” in which I pointed out
that all who combine communism with abolition of the
family also advocate communal houses for large numbers, with communal
kitchens, dining-rooms, and nurseries. This system may be described as
monasteries without celibacy.
There are three kinds of government that are good:
monarchy, aristocracy, and constitutional government (or polity); there are
three that are bad: tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy.
The three
things needed to prevent revolution are government
propaganda in education, respect for law, even in small things, and
justice in law and administration
pan
class=“important”>All social inequality, in the long run, is inequality of
income.
Aristotle’s
most important work in logic is the doctrine of the syllogism. A syllogism is
an argument consisting of three parts, a major premiss, a minor premiss, and
a conclusion.
The temples, in the Hellenistic world, were the bankers;
they owned the gold reserve, and controlled credit. In the early third
century, the temple of Apollo at Delos made loans at ten per cent; formerly,
the rate of interest had been higher.
Why trouble
about the future? It is wholly uncertain. You may as well enjoy the present;
“What’s to come is still unsure.” For these reasons, Scepticism enjoyed a
considerable popular success.
It is no wonder that the
Epicureans contributed practically nothing to
natural knowledge. They served a useful purpose by their protest against the
increasing devotion of the later pagans to magic, astrology, and divination;
but they remained, like their founder, dogmatic,
limited, and without genuine interest in anything outside individual
happiness.
Socrates was the chief saint of the Stoics throughout their
history; his attitude at the time of his trial, his refusal to escape,
his calmness in the face of death, and his contention that the perpetrator of
injustice injures himself more than his victim, all fitted in perfectly with
Stoic teaching. So did his indifference to heat and cold, his plainness in
matters of food and dress, and his complete independence of all bodily
comforts.
suitable drugs forcibly administered, willpower can be
destroyed. Take Epictetus’s favorite case, the man unjustly
imprisoned by a tyrant, of which there have been more examples in recent
years than at any other period in human history. Some of these men have acted
with Stoic heroism; some, rather mysteriously, have not. It has become clear,
not only that sufficient torture will break down almost any man’s fortitude,
but also that morphia or cocaine can reduce a man to docility. The will, in fact, is only independent of the tyrant so
long as the tyrant is unscientific.
Third: the
importance of the long Roman peace in diffusing culture and in accustoming
men to the idea of a single civilization associated
with a single government.
To understand Marx psychologically, one should use
the following dictionary:
Yahweh = Dialectical Materialism
The Messiah = Marx
The Elect = The Proletariat
The Church = The Communist Party
The Second Coming = The Revolution
Hell = Punishment of the Capitalists
The Millennium = The Communist Commonwealth
What follows is an abstract
of the Summa contra Gentiles: Let us first consider what is meant by
“wisdom.” A man may be wise in some particular pursuit, such as making
houses; this implies that he knows the means to some particular end. But all
particular ends are subordinate to the end of the universe, and wisdom per se
is concerned with the end of the universe. Now the
end of the universe is the good of the intellect, i.e., truth. The
pursuit of wisdom in this sense is the most perfect, sublime, profitable, and
delightful of pursuits. All this is proved by appeal to the authority of
“The Philosopher,” i.e., Aristotle.
God is
truth. (This is to be understood literally.)
Matrimony
should be indissoluble, because the father is needed in the education of the
children,
Boniface VIII, in the Bull Unam
Sanctam, made more extreme claims than had ever been made by any previous
Pope. He instituted, in 1300, the year of Jubilee,
when plenary indulgence is granted to all Catholics who visit Rome and
perform certain ceremonies while there. This brought immense sums of money
to the coffers of the Curia and the pockets of the Roman people. There was to
be a Jubilee every hundredth year, but the profits were so great that the
period was shortened to fifty years, and then to twenty-five, at which it
remains to the present day.
This
form of government, however, if it spreads, must obviously bring with
it a new form of culture; the culture with which we shall be concerned is in the main “liberal," that is
to say, of the kind most naturally associated with commerce. To this there
are important exceptions, especially in Germany; Fichte and Hegel, to take
two examples, have an outlook which is totally unconnected with commerce.
But such exceptions are not typical of their age.
Modern philosophy, however, has retained, for the most
part, an individualistic and subjective character. This is very marked
in Descartes, who builds up all knowledge from the certainty of his own
existence, and accepts clearness and distinctness (both subjective) as
criteria of truth. It is not prominent in Spinoza, but reappears in Leibniz’s
windowless monads. Locke, whose temperament is thoroughly objective, is
forced reluctantly into the subjective doctrine that knowledge is of the
agreement or disagreement of ideas–a view so repulsive to him that he
escapes from it by violent inconsistencies. Berkeley, after abolishing
matter, is only saved from complete subjectivism by a use of God which most
subsequent philosophers have regarded as illegitimate. In Hume, the
empiricist philosophy culminated in a scepticism which none could refute and
none could accept. Kant and Fichte were subjective in temperament as well as
in doctrine; Hegel saved himself by means of the influence of Spinoza.
Rousseau and the romantic movement extended subjectivity from theory of
knowledge to ethics and politics, and ended, logically, in complete anarchism
such as that of Bakunin. This extreme of subjectivism
is a form of madness.
The Renaissance was not a popular movement; it was a
movement of a small number of scholars and artists, encouraged by liberal
patrons, especially the Medici and the humanist popes.
It is true that
power, often, depends upon opinion, and opinion upon
propaganda; it is true, also, that it is an advantage in propaganda to
seem more virtuous than your adversary, and that one way of seeming virtuous
is to be virtuous.
Raphael Hythloday [the protagonist of Utopia] relates that he preached
Christianity to the Utopians, and that many were converted when they learnt
that Christ was opposed to private property. The importance of communism is
constantly stressed; almost at the end we are told that in all other nations
“I can perceive nothing but a certain conspiracy of
rich men procuring their own commodities under the name and title of the
common wealth."
Diversity is essential to happiness, and in Utopia there is
hardly any. This is a defect of all planned social systems, actual as well as
imaginary.
Protestant success, at first
amazingly rapid, was checked mainly as a resultant of Loyola’s creation of the Jesuit order. Loyola had
been a soldier, and his order was founded on military models; there must be
unquestioning obedience to the General, and every Jesuit was to consider
himself engaged in warfare against heresy. As early as the Council of Trent,
the Jesuits began to be influential. They were disciplined, able, completely
devoted to the cause, and skilful propagandists. Their theology was the
opposite of that of the Protestants; they rejected those elements of Saint
Augustine’s teaching which the Protestants emphasized. They believed in free will, and opposed predestination.
Salvation was not by faith alone, but by both faith and works.
They concentrated on education, and thus acquired a firm
hold on the minds of the young. Whenever theology did not interfere,
the education they gave was the best obtainable; we shall see that they
taught Descartes more mathematics than he would have learnt elsewhere.
Hobbes considers the
question why men cannot co-operate like ants and bees. Bees in the same
hive, he says, do not compete; they have no desire for honour; and they do
not use reason to criticize the government. Their
agreement is natural, but that of men can only be artificial, by covenant.
The covenant must confer power on one man or one assembly, since otherwise it
cannot be enforced. “Covenants, without the sword, are but words." (
President Wilson unfortunately forgot this.) The covenant is not, as
afterwards in Locke and Rousseau, between the citizens and the ruling power;
it is a covenant made by the citizens with each other to obey such ruling
power as the majority shall choose. When they have chosen, their political
power is at an end. The minority is as much bound as the majority, since the
covenant was to obey the government chosen by the majority. When the government has been chosen, the citizens lose all
rights except such as the government may find it expedient to grant. There is
no right of rebellion, because the ruler is not bound by any contract,
whereas the subjects are.
He regarded the bodies of men and animals as machines;
animals he regarded as automata, governed entirely by the laws of physics,
and devoid of feeling or consciousness. Men are different: they have a
soul, which resides in the pineal gland. There the soul comes in
contact with the “vital spirits,” and through this contact there is
interaction between soul and body. The total quantity of motion in the
universe is constant, and therefore the soul cannot affect it; but it can
alter the direction of motion of the animal spirits, and hence, indirectly,
of other parts of the body.
Spinoza does not, like
the Stoics, object to all emotions; he objects only to those that are
“passions,” i.e., those in which we appear to ourselves to be passive in the
power of outside forces. “An emotion which is a passion ceases to be a
passion as soon as we form a clear and distinct idea of it.” Understanding
that all things are necessary helps the mind to acquire power over the
emotions. “He who clearly and distinctly understands
himself and his emotions, loves God, and so much the more as he more
understands himself and his emotions." This proposition introduces us
to the “intellectual love of God,” in which wisdom consists. The intellectual
love of God is a union of thought and emotion: it consists, I think one may
say, in true thought combined with joy in the apprehension of truth.
Every increase in the understanding of what happens to us
consists in referring events to the idea of God, since, in truth, everything
is part of God. This understanding of everything as part of God is love of
God. When all objects are referred to God, the idea of God will fully occupy
the mind.
The hereditary principle has almost vanished from
politics.
Throughout the Middle Ages, the law of nature was held to
condemn “usury,” i.e., lending money at interest. Church property was
almost entirely in land, and landowners have always been borrowers rather
than lenders. But when Protestantism arose, its
support–especially the support of Calvinism–came chiefly from the
rich middle class, who were lenders rather than borrowers. Accordingly first
Calvin, then other Protestants, and finally the Catholic Church, sanctioned
“usury.”
As a rule, the man who first thinks of a new idea is so
much ahead of his time that every one thinks him silly, so that he
remains obscure and is soon forgotten. Then, gradually, the world becomes
ready for the idea, and the man who proclaims it at the fortunate moment gets
all the credit.
A new
international Social Contract is necessary before we can enjoy the promised
benefits of government. When once an international government has been
created, much of Locke’s political philosophy will again become
applicable, though not the part of it that deals with private
property.
both in England and in America, big business on the whole
dislikes war.
- WHAT?! The military industrial complex. War
profiteering. This is an outlandish statement. There is no excuse for this
nonsense, even in the day when it was written, circa WW2.
”…the truth of my hypothesis,
that all our reasonings concerning causes and effects
are derived from nothing but custom; and that belief is more properly an act
of the sensitive, than of the cogitative part of our natures."
To this extent, Hume has proved that pure empiricism is not
a sufficient basis for science. But if this one principle is admitted,
everything else can proceed in accordance with the theory that all our
knowledge is based on experience.
Revolt of solitary instincts against social bonds is the
key to the philosophy, the politics, and the sentiments, not only of what is
commonly called the romantic movement, but of its progeny down to the present
day.
The old arguments at least were honest: if valid, they
proved their point; if invalid, it was open to any critic to prove them so.
But the new theology of the heart dispenses with argument; it cannot be
refuted, because it does not profess to prove its points.
What we call democracy he calls elective aristocracy; this,
he says, is the best of all governments, but it is not suitable to all
countries.
The Social Contract became the Bible of most of the leaders
in the French Revolution, but no doubt, as is the fate of Bibles, it
was not carefully read and was still less understood by many of its
disciples.
Kant’s vigour
and freshness of mind in old age are shown by his treatise on Perpetual Peace
(1795). In this work he advocates a federation of free States, bound together
by a covenant forbidding war. Reason, he says,
utterly condemns war, which only an international government can
prevent.
Men are born ignorant, not stupid; they are made stupid by
education.
He [Condorcet] was a believer in the equality of women.
He was also the inventor of Malthus’s theory of
population, which, however, had not for him the gloomy consequences that it
had for Malthus, because he coupled it with the necessity of birth
control. Malthus’s father was a disciple of Condorcet, and it was in
this way that Malthus came to know of the theory.
Marx
himself, though his. doctrines are in some respects pre- Darwinian, wished to
dedicate his book to Darwin.
first, the power of man in
his conflicts with nature, and then the power of
rulers as against the human beings whose beliefs and aspirations they seek to
control by scientific propaganda, especially education. The result is
a diminution of fixity; no change seems impossible. Nature is raw material; so is that part of the human race
which does not effectively participate in government.
Truth and falsehood are not
sharply defined opposites, as is commonly supposed; nothing is wholly false,
and nothing that we can know is wholly true.
Hegel does not mean only
that, in some situations, a nation cannot rightly avoid going to war. He
means much more than this. He is opposed to the
creation of institutions–such as a world government –which would prevent
such situations from arising, because he thinks it a good thing that there
should be wars from time to time. War, he says, is the condition in
which we take seriously the vanity of temporal goods and things. (This view
is to be contrasted with the opposite theory, that all wars have economic
causes.) War has a positive moral value: “War has the higher significance
that through it the moral health of peoples is preserved in their
indifference towards the stabilizing of finite determinations.” Peace is
ossification; the Holy Alliance, and Kant’s League for Peace, are mistaken,
because a family of States needs an enemy.
Conflicts of States can only be decided by war
Nietzsche’s ethic is not one of self-indulgence in any
ordinary sense; he believes in Spartan discipline and the capacity to endure
as well as inflict pain for important ends. He admires strength of will above
all things. “I test the power of a will,” he says, “according to the amount
of resistance it can offer and the amount of pain and torture it can endure
and know how to turn to its own advantage; I do not point to the evil
and pain of existence with the finger of reproach, but rather entertain the
hope that life may one day become more evil and more full of suffering than
it has ever been.” He regards compassion as a weakness to be combated. “The
object is to attain that enormous energy of greatness which can model the man
of the future by means of discipline and also by means of the annihilation of
millions of the bungled and botched, and which can yet avoid going to ruin at
the sight of the suffering created thereby, the like of which has never been
seen before."
Nietzsche is not a
nationalist, and shows no excessive admiration for Germany. He wants an international ruling race, who are to be the
lords of the earth: “a new vast aristocracy based upon the most severe
self-discipline, in which the will of philosophical men of power and
artist-tyrants will be stamped upon thousands of years."
Dr.
Dewey’s world, it seems to me, is one in which human beings occupy the
imagination…
Table of Contents
- Pages numbers from the pdf.
page 11:
- Is there such a thing as wisdom, or is what seems such merely the ultimate
refinement of folly?
page 16:
- What had happened in the great age of Greece happened again in Renaissance
Italy: traditional moral restraints disappeared, because they were seen to be
associated with superstition; the liberation from fetters made individuals
energetic and creative, producing a rare florescence of genius; but the anarchy
and treachery which inevitably resulted from the decay of morals made Italians
collectively impotent, and they fell, like the Greeks,
under the domination of nations less civilized than themselves but not so
destitute of social cohesion.
page 17:
- In Protestant theory, there should be no earthly intermediary between the
soul and God.
page 20:
- Every community is exposed to two opposite dangers:
ossification through too much discipline and reverence for tradition, on the
one hand; on the other hand, dissolution, or subjection to foreign conquest,
through the growth of an individualism and personal independence that makes
co-operation impossible. In general, important civilizations start with
a rigid and superstitious system, gradually relaxed, and leading, at a certain
stage, to a period of brilliant genius, while the good of the old tradition
remains and the evil inherent in its dissolution has not yet developed
Book One: ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
Part I. The Pre-Socratics
page 28:
-
Everything about Homer is conjectural,
-
Guided by anthropology, modern writers have come to the conclusion that
Homer, so far from being primitive, was an expurgator, a kind of
eighteenth-century rationalizer of ancient myths,
page 32:
- Dionysus, or Bacchus, whom we think of most naturally
as the somewhat disreputable god of wine and drunkenness. The way in which, out
of his worship, there arose a profound mysticism, which greatly
influenced many of the philosophers, and even had a part in shaping Christian
theology, is very remarkable, and must be understood by anyone who wishes to
study the development of Greek thought.
page 33:
- The civilized man is distinguished from the savage
mainly by prudence, or, to use a slightly wider term, forethought. He is
willing to endure present pains for the sake of future pleasures, even
if the future pleasures are rather distant.
page 34:
- Prudence versus passion is a conflict that runs through history. It is not a
conflict in which we ought to side wholly with either party.
page 37:
- At Eleusis, where the Eleusinian mysteries formed the
most sacred part of Athenian State religion, a hymn was sung, saying:
With Thy wine-cup waving high, With Thy maddening revelry, To Eleusis’ flowery
vale, Comest Thou–Bacchus, Paean, hail!
page 41:
- the worship of Dionysus, which came from
Thrace, and is barely mentioned in Homer, contained in germ a wholly new way of
looking at man’s relation to the world. It would certainly be wrong to credit
the Thracians themselves with any very exalted views; but there can be no doubt
that, to the Greeks, the phenomenon of ecstasy
suggested that the soul was something more than a feeble double of the self,
and that it was only when ‘out of the body’ that it could show its true
nature….
page 42:
- Thales, who said that everything is made of water.
page 44:
- told by Aristotle in his Politics (1259a): “He [Thales] was reproached for his poverty, which was supposed
to show that philosophy is of no use. According to the story, he knew by his
skill in the stars while it was yet winter that there would be a great harvest
of olives in the coming year; so, having a little money, he gave deposits for
the use of all the olive-presses in Chios and Miletus, which he hired at a low
price because no one bid against him. When the harvest time came, and many were
wanted all at once and of a sudden, he let them out at any rate which he
pleased, and made a quantity of money. Thus he showed the world that
philosophers can easily be rich if they like, but that their ambition is of
another sort.”
page 46:
- The Milesian school is important, not for what it achieved, but for what it
attempted. It was brought into existence by the contact of the Greek mind with
Babylonia and Egypt. Miletus was a rich commercial city, in which primitive
prejudices and superstitions were softened by intercourse with many nations.
Ionia, until its subjugation by Darius at the beginning of the fifth century,
was culturally the most important part of the Hellenic world. It was almost
untouched by the religious movement connected with Bacchus and Orpheus; its
religion was Olympic, but seems to have been not taken very seriously. The
speculations of Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes are to be regarded as
scientific hypotheses, and seldom show any undue intrusion of anthropomorphic
desires and moral ideas.
page 50:
- Pythagoreanism, he [Plato] says, was a movement of
reform in Orphism, and Orphism was a movement of reform in the worship of
Dionysus.
page 51:
- It might seem that the empirical philosopher is the
slave of his material, but that the pure mathematician, like the musician, is a
free creator of his world of ordered beauty.
page 53:
- Pythagoras, as everyone knows, said that “all things
are numbers." This statement, interpreted in a modern way, is logically
nonsense, but what he meant was not exactly nonsense. He discovered the
importance of numbers in music, and the connection which he established between
music and arithmetic survives in the mathematical terms “harmonic mean” and
“harmonic progression.” He thought of numbers as shapes, as they appear on dice
or playing cards. We still speak of squares and cubes
of numbers, which are terms that we owe to him. He also spoke of oblong
numbers, triangular numbers, pyramidal numbers, and so on. These were
the numbers of pebbles (or, as we should more naturally say, shot) required to
make the shapes in question. He presumably thought of the world as atomic, and
of bodies as built up of molecules composed of atoms arranged in various
shapes. In this way he hoped to make arithmetic the fundamental study in
physics as in aesthetics.
page 54:
- Geometry, as established by the Greeks, starts with axioms which are (or are
deemed to be) self-evident, and proceeds, by deductive reasoning, to arrive at
theorems that are very far from self-evident. The axioms and theorems are held
to be true of actual space, which is something given in experience. It thus
appeared to be possible to discover things about the actual world by first
noticing what is self-evident and then using deduction. This view influenced
Plato and Kant, and most of the intermediate philosophers. When the Declaration of Independence says “we hold these
truths to be self evident,” it is modelling itself on Euclid. The
eighteenth-century doctrine of natural rights is a search for Euclidean axioms
in politics.
- “Self-evident” was substituted by Franklin for Jefferson’s “sacred and
undeniable.”
page 55:
- Personal religion is derived from ecstasy, theology
from mathematics; and both are to be found in Pythagoras.
page 57:
- In studying a philosopher, the right attitude is
neither reverence nor contempt, but first a kind of hypothetical sympathy,
until it is possible to know what it feels like to believe in his theories, and
only then a revival of the critical attitude, which should resemble, as far as
possible, the state of mind of a person abandoning opinions which he has
hitherto held. Contempt interferes with the first part of this process, and
reverence with the second. Two things are to be remembered: that a man
whose opinions and theories are worth studying may be presumed to have had some
intelligence, but that no man is likely to have arrived at complete and final
truth on any subject whatever. When an intelligent man expresses a view which
seems to us obviously absurd, we should not attempt to prove that it is somehow
true, but we should try to understand how it ever came to seem true.
page 61:
-
Quotes by Heraclitus:
-
Night-walkers, magicians, priests of Bacchus and priestesses of the wine-vat,
mystery-mongers.
-
The mysteries practised among men are unholy mysteries.
-
For if it were not to Dionysus that they made a procession and sang the
shameful phallic hymn, they would be acting most shamelessly. But Hades is the
same as Dionysus in whose honour they go mad and keep the feast of the
wine-vat.
page 62:
-
The doctrine that everything is in a state of flux is
the most famous of the opinions of Heraclitus, and the one most
emphasised by his disciples, as described in Plato Theaetetus.
-
“You cannot step twice into the same river; for fresh
waters are ever flowing in upon you."
-
“The sun is new every day.”
page 63:
- His [Heraclitus] works, like those of all the
philosophers before Plato, are only known through
quotations, largely made by Plato or Aristotle for the sake of
refutation. When one thinks what would become of any modern philosopher
if he were only known through the polemics of his rivals, one can see how
admirable the pre-Socratics must have been, since even through the mist of
malice spread by their enemies they still appear great. However this may be,
Plato and Aristotle agree that Heraclitus taught that “nothing ever is,
everything is becoming” ( Plato), and that “nothing steadfastly is” (
Aristotle).
page 66:
- The doctrine of Parmenides was set forth in a poem On Nature. He considered the senses deceptive, and condemned the
multitude of sensible things as mere illusion. The only true being is
“the One,” which is infinite and indivisible.
page 68:
- Parmenides assumes that words have a constant meaning; this is really the
basis of his argument, which he supposes unquestionable. But although the dictionary or the encyclopaedia gives what may
be called the official and socially sanctioned meaning of a word, no two people
who use the same word have just the same thought in their minds.
page 77:
-
Athens had lagged behind many other Greek cities; neither in art nor in
literature had it produced any great man (except Solon,
who was primarily a lawgiver).
-
Solomon and Fomenko come to mind immediatly.
page 81:
- Aristotle points out that he only introduces mind as a cause when he knows no
other. Whenever he can, he gives a mechanical explanation.
page 84:
-
It was common in antiquity to reproach the atomists with attributing
everything to chance. They were, on the contrary, strict determinists, who believed that everything happens in
accordance with natural laws. Democritus explicitly denied that anything can
happen by chance.
-
In ethics he [Democritus] considered cheerfulness
the goal of life, and regarded moderation and culture as the best means to it.
He disliked everything violent and passionate; he disapproved of sex, because,
he said, it involved the overwhelming of consciousness by pleasure. He valued
friendship, but thought ill of women, and did not desire children, because
their education interferes with philosophy.
-
“Poverty in a democracy is as much to be preferred to what is called
prosperity under despots as freedom is to slavery,” he [Democritus] says.
page 92:
- There is, however, one important and highly intellectual class which is
concerned with the fence of the plutocracy, namely the class of corporation lawyers. In some respects, their functions are
similar to those that were performed in Athens by the Sophists.
- Athenian democracy, though it had the grave limitation of not including
slaves or women, was in some respects more democratic
than any modern system. Judges and most executive officers were chosen by lot,
and served for short periods; they were thus average citizens, like our
jurymen, with the prejudices and lack of professionalism characteristic of
average citizens. In general, there were a large number of judges to
hear each case. The plaintiff and defendant, or prosecutor and accused,
appeared in person, not through professional lawyers. Naturally, success or
failure depended largely on oratorical skill in appealing to popular
prejudices. Although a man had to deliver his own speech, he could hire an
expert to write the speech for him, or, as many preferred, he could pay for
instruction in the arts required for success in the law courts. These arts the
Sophists were supposed to teach.
page 94:
- There is a story about Protagoras, no doubt apocryphal, which illustrates the
connection of the Sophists with the law-courts in the popular mind. It is said
that he taught a young man on the terms that he should be paid his fee if the
young man won his first law-suit, but not otherwise, and that the young man’s
first law-suit was one brought by Protagoras for recovery of his fee.
page 95:
- The disbelief in objective truth makes the majority,
for practical purposes, the arbiters as to what to believe.
page 96:
-
Those to whom philosophy was a way of life, closely bound up with religion,
were naturally shocked; to them, the Sophists appeared
frivolous and immoral.
-
Plato is always concerned to advocate views that will make people what he
thinks virtuous; he is hardly ever intellectually
honest, because he allows himself to judge doctrines by their social
consequences. Even about this, he is not honest; he pretends to follow the
argument and to be judging by purely theoretical standards, when in fact he is
twisting the discussion so as to lead to a virtuous result. He introduced this
vice into philosophy, where it has persisted ever since.
Part II. Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle
page 100:
- He [Socrates] would ask such questions as: “If I wanted a shoe mended, whom should I employ?” To which
some ingenuous youth would answer: “A shoemaker, O Socrates.” He would go on to
carpenters, coppersmiths, etc., and finally ask some such question as “who
should mend the Ship of State?"
page 106:
- The “Apology” gives a clear picture of a man [Socrates] of a certain type: a man very sure of himself,
high- minded, indifferent to worldly success, believing that he is guided by a
divine voice, and persuaded that clear thinking is the most important requisite
for right living. Except in this last point, he resembles a Christian martyr or
a Puritan.
page 109:
- The close connection between virtue and knowledge is
characteristic of Socrates and Plato. To some degree, it exists in all Greek
thought, as opposed to that of Christianity. In Christian ethics, a pure heart
is the essential, and is at least as likely to be found among the ignorant as
among the learned.
page 110:
- Logical errors are, I think, of greater practical importance than many people
believe; they enable their perpetrators to hold the comfortable opinion on
every subject in turn. Any logically coherent body of doctrine is sure to be in
part painful and contrary to current prejudices.
page 118:
- Of these, Plato was the most important in early Christianity, Aristotle in
the medieval Church; but when, after the Renaissance,
men began to value political freedom, it was above all to Plutarch that they
turned. He influenced profoundly the English and French liberals of the
eighteenth century, and the founders of the United States; he influenced
the romantic movement in Germany, and has continued, mainly by indirect
channels, to influence German thought down to the present day.
page 123:
-
In the third place: much education is needed to make
a good ruler on Plato’s principles. … He was sufficiently Pythagorean
to think that without mathematics no true wisdom is possible. This view implies an oligarchy.
-
In the fourth place: Plato, in common with most Greek
philosophers, took the view that leisure is essential to wisdom, which
will therefore not be found among those who have to work for their living, but
only among those who have independent means, or who are relieved by the state
from anxieties as to their subsistence. This point of view is essentially
aristocratic.
page 128:
- As for economics: Plato proposes a thoroughgoing
communism for the guardians … The guardians are to have small houses
and simple food; they are to live as in a camp, dining together in companies;
they are to have no private property beyond what is absolutely necessary. Gold
and silver are to be forbidden. Though not rich, there is no reason why they
should not be happy; but the purpose of the city is the good of the whole, not
the happiness of one class. Both wealth and poverty are harmful, and in Plato’s
city neither will exist.
- With feigned unwillingness, the Platonic Socrates
proceeds to apply his communism to the family. Friends, he says, should have
all things in common, including women and children. He admits that this
presents difficulties, but thinks them not insuperable. First of all, girls are
to have exactly the same education as boys, learning music, gymnastics, and the
art of war along with the boys. Women are to have
complete equality with men in all respects.
- “These women shall be, without exception, the common
wives of these men, and no one shall have a wife of his own."
- At certain festivals, brides and bridegrooms, in such
numbers as are required to keep the population constant, will be brought
together, by lot, as they will be taught to believe; but in fact the rulers of
the city will manipulate the lots on eugenic principles.
page 129:
- All children will be taken away from their parents at
birth, and great care will be taken that no parents shall know who are their
children, and no children shall know who are their parents.
- intercourse is to be free, but abortion or
infanticide is to be compulsory.
page 130:
- Lying, Plato says explicitly, is to be a prerogative
of the government, just as giving medicine is of physicians.
page 131:
- The first suggested definition of “justice,” at the
beginning of the Republic, is that it consists in paying debts. This
definition is soon abandoned as inadequate, but something of it remains at the
end.
page 133:
- On questions of fact, we can appeal to science and scientific methods of
observation; but on ultimate questions of ethics there seems to be nothing
analogous. Yet, if this is really the case, ethical
disputes resolve themselves into contests for power– including propaganda
power.
page 134:
-
Thrasymachus proclaims emphatically that “justice is
nothing else than the interest of the stronger."
-
Is there any standard of “good” and “bad,” except what the man using these
words desires? If there is not, many of the consequences drawn by Thrasymachus
seem inescapable.
page 137:
- Why did the Puritans object to the music and painting and gorgeous ritual of
the Catholic Church? You will find the answer in the tenth book of the
Republic. Why are children in school compelled to learn arithmetic? The reasons
are given in the seventh book.
page 139:
-
But whatever Socrates may say, it remains the case, as any one can see, that
people who stick to philosophy become strange monsters,
not to say utter rogues; even the best of them are made useless by
philosophy.
-
Socrates admits that this is true in the world as it is, but maintains that
it is the other people who are to blame, not the philosophers; in a wise
community the philosophers would not seem foolish; it
is only among fools that the wise are judged to be destitute of wisdom.
page 141:
- We saw that God made only one bed, and it would be
natural to suppose that he made only one straight line. But if there is a
heavenly triangle, he must have made at least three straight lines. The
objects of geometry, though ideal, must exist in many examples; we need the
possibility of two intersecting circles, and so on.
page 148:
-
Plato proceeds to an interesting sketch of the education proper to a young
man who is to be a guardian. We saw that the young man is selected for this
honour on the ground of a combination of intellectual and moral qualities: he
must be just and gentle, fond of learning, with a good memory and a harmonious
mind. The young man who has been chosen for these merits will spend the years from twenty to thirty on the four Pythagorean
studies: arithmetic, geometry (plane and solid), astronomy, and harmony.
-
Essentially the quadrivium (harmony = music).
-
Aristarchus of Samos found such a hypothesis: that all the planets, including
the earth, go round the sun in circles. This view was rejected for two thousand
years, partly on the authority of Aristotle,
-
This piece of scientific history illustrates a general maxim: that any
hypothesis, however absurd, may be useful in science, if it enables a
discoverer to conceive things in a new way; but that, when it has served this
purpose by luck, it is likely to become an obstacle to further advance.
page 149:
- It is noteworthy that modern Platonists, almost without exception, are
ignorant of mathematics, in spite of the immense importance that Plato attached
to arithmetic and geometry, and the immense influence that they had on his
philosophy. This is an example of the evils of
specialization: a man must not write on Plato unless he has spent so much of
his youth on Greek as to have had no time for the things that Plato thought
important.
page 155:
- There is one true coin for which all things ought to be exchanged, and that
is wisdom.
page 161:
- “God desired that all things should be good, and nothing bad, as far as
possible.” “Finding the whole visible sphere not at rest, but moving in an
irregular and disorderly fashion, out of disorder he brought order.” (Thus it
appears that Plato’s God, unlike the Jewish and Christian God, did not create
the world out of nothing, but rearranged pre-existing material.)
page 166:
- Most modern men take it for granted that empirical knowledge is dependent
upon, or derived from, perception. There is, however, in Plato and among
philosophers of certain other schools, a very different doctrine, to the effect
that there is nothing worthy to be called “knowledge” to be derived from the
senses, and that the only real knowledge has to do with concepts. In this view,
“2 + 2 = 4” is genuine knowledge, but such a statement as “snow is white” is so
full of ambiguity and uncertainty that it cannot find a place in the
philosopher’s corpus of truths.
page 169:
- What the above argument amounts to is that, whatever else may be in perpetual
flux, the meanings of words must be fixed, at least for
a time, since otherwise no assertion is definite, and no assertion is true
rather than false. There must be something more or less constant, if discourse
and knowledge are to be possible.
page 176:
- unless words, to some extent, had fixed meanings,
discourse would be impossible. Here again, however, it is easy to be too
absolute. Words do change their meanings; take, for example, the word “idea.”
It is only by a considerable process of education that we learn to give to this
word something like the meaning which Plato gave to it. It is necessary that
the changes in the meanings of words should be slower than the changes that the
words describe; but it is not necessary that there should be no changes in the
meanings of words
page 184:
-
It will be seen that this doctrine is optimistic and teleological: the universe and everything in it is developing towards
something continually better than what went before.
-
There are, he says, three kinds of substances: those that are sensible and
perishable, those that are sensible but not perishable, and those that are
neither sensible nor perishable. The first class includes plants and animals,
the second includes the heavenly bodies (which Aristotle believed to undergo no
change except motion), the third includes the rational soul in man, and also
God.
page 186:
-
The world is continually evolving towards a greater
degree of form, and thus becoming progressively more like God. But the process
cannot be completed, because matter cannot be wholly eliminated. This is a
religion of progress and evolution…
-
Is this the foundation of Teilhard’s
Omega-Point?
page 202:
- In order of time, the family comes first; it
is built on the two fundamental relations of man and woman, master and slave,
both of which are natural.
page 203:
- A State being composed of households, each of which consists of one family,
the discussion of politics should begin with the family.
page 204:
- The natural way to get wealth is by skilful management of house and land. To
the wealth that can be made in this way there is a limit, but to what can be
made by trade there is none. Trade has to do with money, but wealth is not the
acquisition of coin. Wealth derived from trade is
justly hated, because it is unnatural. “The most hated sort, and with the
greatest reason, is usury, which makes a gain out of money itself, and not from
the natural object of it. For money was intended to be used in exchange, but
not to increase at interest. . . . Of all modes of getting wealth this is the
most unnatural”
page 205:
- Next comes the kind of argument against the proposed abolition of the family
that naturally occurs to every reader.
- I wrote an essay once, called “Architecture and the Social System,” in which
I pointed out that all who combine communism with
abolition of the family also advocate communal houses for large numbers, with
communal kitchens, dining-rooms, and nurseries. This system may be described as
monasteries without celibacy.
page 206:
- There are three kinds of government that are good:
monarchy, aristocracy, and constitutional government (or polity); there are
three that are bad: tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy.
page 207:
- Monarchy is better than aristocracy, aristocracy is better than polity. But
the corruption of the best is worst; therefore tyranny is worse than oligarchy,
and oligarchy than democracy.
page 208:
- The three things needed to prevent revolution are
government propaganda in education, respect for law, even in small
things, and justice in law and administration
All social inequality, in the long run, is inequality
of income.
- A tyrant desires riches, whereas a king desires
honour. The tyrant has guards who are mercenaries, whereas the king has
guards who are citizens.
page 212:
- Aristotle, on the contrary, is still, especially in logic, a battle-ground,
and cannot be treated in a purely historical spirit.
page 213:
-
Aristotle’s most important work in logic is the
doctrine of the syllogism. A syllogism is an argument consisting of three
parts, a major premiss, a minor premiss, and a conclusion.
-
All men are mortal (Major premiss). Socrates is a man (Minor premiss).
Therefore: Socrates is mortal (Conclusion). Or: All men are mortal. All Greeks
are men. Therefore: All Greeks are mortal.
page 216:
- All the important inferences outside logic and pure mathematics are
inductive, not deductive; the only exceptions are law and theology, each of
which derives its first principles from an unquestionable text, viz. the
statute books or the scriptures.
page 219:
- I conclude that the Aristotelian doctrines with which we have been concerned
in this chapter are wholly false, with the exception of the formal theory of
the syllogism, which is unimportant. Any person in the present day who wishes
to learn logic will be wasting his time if he reads Aristotle or any of his
disciples.
Part III. Ancient Philosophy after Aristotle
page 236:
- Plato and Aristotle thought it wrong to make slaves of Greeks, but not of
barbarians. Alexander, who was not quite a Greek, tried to break down this
attitude of superiority. He himself married two
barbarian princesses, and he compelled his leading Macedonians to marry Persian
women of noble birth.
page 241:
- The temples, in the Hellenistic world, were the
bankers; they owned the gold reserve, and controlled credit. In the early third
century, the temple of Apollo at Delos made loans at ten per cent; formerly,
the rate of interest had been higher.
page 248:
- Diogenes personally was a man full of vigour,
but his doctrine, like all those of the Hellenistic age, was one to appeal to
weary men, in whom disappointment had destroyed natural zest. And it was
certainly not a doctrine calculated to promote at or science or statesmanship,
or any useful activity except one of protest against
powerful evil.
page 249:
- The Sophists, notably Protagoras and Gorgias, had
been led by the ambiguities and. apparent contradictions of sense-perception to
a subjectivism not unlike Hume’s.
- Why trouble about the future? It is wholly uncertain.
You may as well enjoy the present; “What’s to come is still unsure.” For these
reasons, Scepticism enjoyed a considerable popular success.
page 251:
- In some respects, the doctrine of Timon was very similar to that of Hume.
page 252:
- in fact, none seem to have learnt anything except
cleverness and indifference to truth. So great was the influence of
Arcesilaus that the Academy remained sceptical for about two hundred
years.
page 253:
-
Cato, who represented the stern, stiff, stupid, and brutal moral code by
means of which Rome had defeated Carthage. From youth to old age, he lived
simply, rose early, practised severe manual labour, ate only coarse food, and
never wore a gown that cost over a hundred pence. Towards the State he was
scrupulously honest, avoiding all bribery and plunder. He exacted of other
Romans all the virtues that he practised himself, and asserted that to accuse
and pursue the wicked was the best thing an honest man could do. He enforced,
as far as he could, the old Roman severity of manners:
-
“Cato put out of the Senate also, one Manilius, who was in great towardness
to have been made Consul the next year following, only because he kissed his
wife too lovingly in the day time, and before his daughter: and reproving him
for it, he told him, his wife never kissed him, but when it thundered.”*
-
When he was in power, he put down luxury and feasting. He made his wife
suckle not only her own children, but also those of his slaves, in order that,
having been nourished by the same milk, they might love his children. When his
slaves were too old to work, he sold them remorselessly. He insisted that his
slaves should always be either working or sleeping. He encouraged his slaves to
quarrel with each other, for “he could not abide that they should be friends.”
When a slave had committed a grave fault, he would call in his other slaves,
and induce them to condemn the delinquent to death; he would then carry out the
sentence with his own hands in the presence of the survivors.
-
The Athenians, in Cato’s view, were a lesser breed
without the law; it did not matter if they were degraded by the shallow
sophistics of intellectuals, but the Roman youth must
be kept puritanical, imperialistic, ruthless, and stupid.
page 259:
-
He is thus led, in practice, to regarding absence of pain, rather than
presence of pleasure, as the wise man’s goal. * The stomach may be at the root
of things, but the pains of stomach ache outweigh the pleasures of gluttony;
accordingly Epicurus lived on bread, with a little cheese on feast days.
-
“The greatest good of all is prudence: it is a more precious thing even than
philosophy.” -Epicurus
page 260:
- The wise man will try to live unnoticed, so as to have no enemies.
page 261:
- Epicurus was a materialist, but not a determinist.
- It is no wonder that the Epicureans
contributed practically nothing to natural knowledge. They served a useful
purpose by their protest against the increasing devotion of the later pagans to
magic, astrology, and divination; but they remained, like their founder, dogmatic, limited, and without genuine interest in anything
outside individual happiness.
page 267:
page 268:
- Socrates was the chief saint of the Stoics throughout
their history; his attitude at the time of his trial, his refusal to
escape, his calmness in the face of death, and his contention that the
perpetrator of injustice injures himself more than his victim, all fitted in
perfectly with Stoic teaching. So did his indifference to heat and cold, his
plainness in matters of food and dress, and his complete independence of all
bodily comforts.
page 269:
- All things are parts of one single system, which is called Nature
page 282:
- suitable drugs forcibly administered, willpower can
be destroyed. Take Epictetus’s favorite case, the man unjustly
imprisoned by a tyrant, of which there have been more examples in recent years
than at any other period in human history. Some of these men have acted with
Stoic heroism; some, rather mysteriously, have not. It has become clear, not
only that sufficient torture will break down almost any man’s fortitude, but
also that morphia or cocaine can reduce a man to docility. The will, in fact, is only independent of the tyrant so long
as the tyrant is unscientific.
page 283:
- Kant, whose ethical system is very similar to that of the Stoics.
page 285:
- The doctrine of natural right, as it appears in the sixteenth, seventeenth,
and eighteenth centuries, is a revival of a Stoic doctrine, though with
important modifications.
page 285:
- Third: the importance of the long Roman peace in diffusing culture and in
accustoming men to the idea of a single civilization
associated with a single government.
page 296:
- Constantine’s adoption of Christianity was politically successful, whereas
earlier attempts to introduce a new religion failed
page 304:
We now come to the Second Person, whom Plotinus calls nous. It is always difficult to find an English word
to represent nous. The standard dictionary translation is “mind,” but this does
not have the correct connotations, particularly when the word is used in a
religious philosophy. If we were to say that Plotinus put mind above soul, we
should give a completely wrong impression. McKenna, the translator of Plotinus,
uses “Intellectual-Principle,” but this is awkward, and does not suggest an
object suitable for religious veneration. Dean Inge uses “Spirit,” which is
perhaps the best word available. But it leaves out the intellectual element
which was important in all Greek religious philosophy after Pythagoras.
Mathematics, the world of ideas, and all thought about what is not sensible,
have, for Pythagoras, Plato, and Plotinus, something divine; they constitute
the activity of nous, or at least the nearest approach to its activity that we
can conceive. It was this intellectual element in Plato’s religion that led
Christians–notably the author of Saint John’s Gospel–to identify Christ with
the Logos. Logos should be translated “reason” in this connection; this
prevents us from using “reason” as the translation of nous. I shall follow Dean
Inge in using “Spirit,” but with the proviso that nous has an intellectual
connotation which is absent from “Spirit” as usually understood. But often I
shall use the word nous untranslated.
page 312:
- Plotinus is both an end and a beginning–an end as regards the Greeks, a
beginning as regards Christendom.
Book Two: CATHOLIC PHILOSOPHY
Part I. The Fathers
page 319:
- The early history of the Israelites cannot be confirmed from any source
outside the Old Testament, and it is impossible to know at what point it ceases
to be purely legendary.
page 321:
- The prophets, on the whole, were fiercely nationalistic, and looked forward
to the day when the Lord would utterly destroy the gentiles.
page 322:
- When Ezra and Nehemiah came back to Jerusalem after the captivity, they were
shocked to find that mixed marriages had been common, and they dissolved all
such marriages.
page 342:
- Four men are called the Doctors of the Western Church: SaintAmbrose, Saint
Jerome, Saint Augustine, and Pope Gregory the Great.
page 362:
- “What, then, is time?” he asks. “If no one asks of me, I know; if I wish to
explain to him who asks, I know not.” Various difficulties perplex him. Neither
past nor future, he says, but only the present, really is; the present is only
a moment, and time can only be measured while it is passing. Nevertheless,
there really is time past and future. We seem here to be led into
contradictions. The only way Augustine can find to avoid these contradictions
is to say that past and future can only be thought of as present: “past” must
be identified with memory, and “future” with expectation, memory and
expectation being both present facts. There are, he
says, three times: “a present of things past, a present of things present, and
a present of things future.” “The present of things past is memory; the present
of things present is sight; and the present of things future is
expectation." To say that there are three times, past, present, and
future, is a loose way of speaking.
page 364:
- there are many, the Saint says, who, during the sack,[of
Rome] sought sanctuary in the churches, which the Goths, because they
were Christians, respected.
page 371:
- To understand Marx psychologically, one should use
the following dictionary:
Yahweh = Dialectical Materialism
The Messiah = Marx
The Elect = The Proletariat
The Church = The Communist Party
The Second Coming = The Revolution
Hell = Punishment of the Capitalists
The Millennium = The Communist Commonwealth
page 372:
- The terms on the left give the emotional content of the terms on the right,
and it is this emotional content, familiar to those who have had a Christian or
a Jewish upbringing, that makes Marx’s eschatology credible. A similar
dictionary could be made for the Nazis, but their conceptions are more purely
Old Testament and less Christian than those of Marx, and their Messiah is more
analogous to the Maccabees than to Christ.
page 377:
- During the sixth century, there were four men of great importance in the
history of culture: Boethius, Justinian, Benedict, and Gregory the Great.
page 383:
- At first, monasticism was a spontaneous movement, quite outside Church
organization. It was Saint Athanasius who reconciled ecclesiastics to it.
Partly as a result of his influence, it came to be the rule that monks should
be priests.
page 388:
- All three, certainly, had a profound effect on future ages: Justinian by his
Laws (not by his conquests, which were ephemeral); Benedict by his monastic
order; and Gregory by the increase of papal power which he brought about.
page 394:
- Roman law, monasticism, and the papacy owe their long and profound influence
very largely to Justinian, Benedict, and Gregory.
Part II. The Schoolmen
page 404:
- The year 1000 may be conveniently taken as marking
the end of the lowest depth to which the civilization of Western Europe sank.
From this point the upward movement began which continued till 1914. In the
beginning, progress was mainly due to monastic reform. Outside the monastic
orders, the clergy had become, for the most part, violent, immoral, and
worldly; they were corrupted by the wealth and power that they owed to
the benefactions of the pious. The same thing happened, over and over again,
even to the monastic orders; but reformers, with new zeal, revived their moral
force as often as it had decayed.
page 405:
- Our use of the phrase the “Dark Ages” to cover the period from 600 to 1000
marks our undue concentration on Western Europe. In China, this period includes
the time of the Tang dynasty, the greatest age of Chinese poetry, and in many
other ways a most remarkable epoch. From India to Spain, the brilliant
civilization of Islam flourished. What was lost to Christendom at this time was
not lost to civilization, but quite the contrary.
page 406:
- It seems not unlikely that, during the next few
centuries, civilization, if it survives, will have greater diversity
than it has had since the Renaissance. There is an imperialism of culture which
is harder to overcome than the imperialism of power.
page 411:
-
God is the beginning, middle, and end of things. God’s essence is unknowable
to men, and even to angels. Even to Himself He is, in a sense, unknowable:
“God does not know Himself, what He is, because He is not a what; in a certain
respect He is incomprehensible to Himself and to every intellect.”
-
Evil does not have its ground in God, for in God there is no idea of evil.
Evil is not-being and has no ground, for if it had a ground it would be
necessary. Evil is a privation of good.
page 416:
- In the 11th century, the reforms led to celibacy of
priests, who, until then, were free to marry.
page 423:
-
Saint Anselm was, like Lanfranc, an Italian, a monk at Bec, and archbishop of
Canterbury ( 1093- 1109), in which capacity he followed the principles of
Gregory VII and quarrelled with the king. He is chiefly known to fame as the
inventor of the “ontological argument” for the existence of God. As he put it,
the argument is as follows: We define “God” as the
greatest possible object of thought. Now if an object of thought does not
exist, another, exactly like it, which does exist, is greater. Therefore the
greatest of all objects of thought must exist, since, otherwise, another, still
greater, would be possible. Therefore God exists.
-
This argument has never been accepted by
theologians. It was adversely criticized at the time; then it was
forgotten till the latter half of the thirteenth century. Thomas Aquinas
rejected it, and among theologians his authority has prevailed ever since.
But among philosophers it has had a better fate.
Descartes revived it in a somewhat amended form; Leibniz thought that it could
be made valid by the addition of a supplement to prove that God is possible.
Kant considered that he had demolished it once for all. Nevertheless, in some
sense, it underlies the system of Hegel and his followers, and reappears in
Bradley’s principle: “What may be and must be, is.”
page 429:
- Omar Khayyám, the only man known to me who was both a poet and a
mathematician
page 445:
- In matters outside the faith, he [John of
Salisbury] was a man of sceptical temper; he called himself an Academic
(in the sense in which Saint Augustine uses this term). His respect for kings
was limited: “an illiterate king is a crowned
ass." He revered Saint Bernard, but was well aware that his attempt to
reconcile Plato and Aristotle must be a failure. He admired Abeélard, but
laughed at his theory of universals, and at Roscelin’s equally. He thought
logic a good introduction to learning, but in itself
bloodless and sterile. Aristotle, he says, can be improved on, even in logic;
respect for ancient authors should not hamper the critical exercise of
reason. Plato is still to him the “prince of all philosophers.”
page 454:
- in 1233 Gregory IX founded the Inquisition, to take over this part of the
work of the episcopate. After 1254, those accused by the Inquisition were not
allowed counsel. If condemned, their property was confiscated–in France, to
the crown. When an accused person was found guilty, he was handed over to the
secular arm with a prayer that his life might be spared; but if the secular
authorities failed to burn him, they were liable to be themselves brought
before the Inquisition. It dealt not only with heresy in the ordinary sense,
but with sorcery and witchcraft. In Spain, it was mainly directed against
crypto-Jews.
page 458:
-
What follows is an abstract of the Summa contra Gentiles: Let us first
consider what is meant by “wisdom.” A man may be wise in some particular
pursuit, such as making houses; this implies that he knows the means to some
particular end. But all particular ends are subordinate to the end of the
universe, and wisdom per se is concerned with the end of the universe. Now
the end of the universe is the good of the intellect,
i.e., truth. The pursuit of wisdom in this sense is the most perfect,
sublime, profitable, and delightful of pursuits. All this is proved by appeal
to the authority of “The Philosopher,” i.e., Aristotle.
-
In the Summa Theologiae, five proofs of God’s
existence are given. First, the argument of the unmoved mover, as above.
Second, the argument of the. First Cause, which again depends upon the
impossibility of an infinite regress. Third, that there must be an ultimate
source of all necessity; this is much the same as the second argument. Fourth,
that we find various perfections in the world, and that these must have their
source in something completely perfect. Fifth, that we find even lifeless
things serving a purpose, which must be that of some being outside them, since
only living things can have an internal purpose.
page 460:
- God is truth. (This is to be understood
literally.)
page 461:
- He [God] knows trivial things, because nothing is
wholly trivial, and everything has some nobility; otherwise God would know only
Himself. Moreover the order of the universe is very noble, and this cannot be
known without knowing even the trivial parts. Finally, God knows evil things, because knowing anything good involves
knowing the opposite evil.
page 462:
- (There is a grave objection, which troubled Saint Augustine, and that is as
to the transmission of original sin. It is the soul that sins, and if the soul
is not transmitted, but created afresh, how can it inherit the sin of Adam?
This is not discussed.)
page 463:
- Matrimony should be indissoluble, because the father
is needed in the education of the children,
page 464:
- There is a most lively and interesting discussion of voluntary poverty,
which, as one might expect, arrives ultimately at a conclusion in harmony with
the principles of the mendicant orders, but states the objections with a force
and realism which shows them to be such as he had actually heard urged by the
secular clergy.
page 465:
- What is to happen, asks the Saint, to a man who never, throughout his life,
ate anything but human flesh, and whose parents did likewise? It would seem
unfair to his victims that they should be deprived of their bodies at the last
day as a consequence of his greed; yet, if not, what will be left to make up
his body; I am happy to say that this difficulty, which might at first sight
seem insuperable, is triumphantly met. The identity of the body, Saint Thomas
points out, is not dependent on the persistence of the same material particles;
during life, by the processes of eating and digesting, the matter composing the
body undergoes perpetual change. The cannibal may, therefore, receive the same
body at the resurrection, even if it is not composed of the same matter as was
in his body when he died. With this comforting thought we may end our abstract
of the Summa contra Gentiles.
page 467:
- There is little of the true philosophic spirit in
Aquinas. He does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever
the argument may lead. He is not engaged in an inquiry, the result of which it
is impossible to know in advance. Before he begins to philosophize, he already
knows the truth; it is declared in the Catholic faith. If he can find
apparently rational arguments for some parts of the faith, so much the better;
if he cannot, he need only fall back on revelation. The finding of arguments
for a conclusion given in advance is not philosophy, but special pleading. I
cannot, therefore, feel that he deserves to be put on a level with the best
philosophers either of Greece or of modern times.
page 473:
- Dante (1265-1321), though as a poet he was a great innovator, was, as a
thinker, somewhat behind the times. His book De Monarchia is Ghibelline in
outlook, and would have been more timely a hundred years earlier. He regards
Emperor and Pope as independent, and both divinely appointed. In the Divine
Comedy, his Satan has three mouths, in which he eternally chews Judas Iscariot,
Brutus, and Cassius, who are all three equally traitors, the first against
Christ, the other two against Caesar. Dante’s thought is interesting, not only
in itself, but as that of a layman; but it was not influential, and was
hopelessly out of date.
page 476:
- Occam is best known for a maxim which is not to be found in his works, but
has acquired the name of “Occam’s razor." This
maxim says: “Entities are not to be multiplied without necessity.” Although he
did not say this, he said something which has much the same effect, namely: “It
is vain to do with more what can be done with fewer.” That is to say, if
everything in some science can be interpreted without assuming this or that
hypothetical entity, there is no ground for assuming it. I have myself found
this a most fruitful principle in logical analysis.
page 479:
- By insisting on the possibility of studying logic and human knowledge without
reference to metaphysics and theology, Occam’s work encouraged scientific
research.
page 483:
- Boniface VIII, in the Bull Unam Sanctam, made more extreme claims than had
ever been made by any previous Pope. He instituted, in
1300, the year of Jubilee, when plenary indulgence is granted to all Catholics
who visit Rome and perform certain ceremonies while there. This brought
immense sums of money to the coffers of the Curia and the pockets of the Roman
people. There was to be a Jubilee every hundredth year, but the profits were so
great that the period was shortened to fifty years, and then to twenty-five, at
which it remains to the present day.
page 489:
- The Peasants’ Revolt of 1381, led by Wat
Tyler, made matters more difficult for Wycliffe. There is no evidence
that he actively encouraged it, but, unlike Luther in similar circumstances, he
refrained from condemning it.
Book Three: MODERN PHILOSOPHY
Part I. From the Renaissance to Hume
page 491:
- States increasingly replace the Church as the governmental authority that
controls culture.
page 492:
- This form of government, however, if it
spreads, must obviously bring with it a new form of culture; the culture with
which we shall be concerned is in the main
“liberal," that is to say, of the kind most naturally associated with
commerce. To this there are important exceptions, especially in Germany; Fichte
and Hegel, to take two examples, have an outlook which is totally unconnected
with commerce. But such exceptions are not typical of their age.
page 493:
- Modern philosophy, however, has retained, for the
most part, an individualistic and subjective character. This is very
marked in Descartes, who builds up all knowledge from the certainty of his own
existence, and accepts clearness and distinctness (both subjective) as criteria
of truth. It is not prominent in Spinoza, but reappears in Leibniz’s windowless
monads. Locke, whose temperament is thoroughly objective, is forced reluctantly
into the subjective doctrine that knowledge is of the agreement or disagreement
of ideas–a view so repulsive to him that he escapes from it by violent
inconsistencies. Berkeley, after abolishing matter, is only saved from complete
subjectivism by a use of God which most subsequent philosophers have regarded
as illegitimate. In Hume, the empiricist philosophy culminated in a scepticism
which none could refute and none could accept. Kant and Fichte were subjective
in temperament as well as in doctrine; Hegel saved himself by means of the
influence of Spinoza. Rousseau and the romantic movement extended subjectivity
from theory of knowledge to ethics and politics, and ended, logically, in
complete anarchism such as that of Bakunin. This
extreme of subjectivism is a form of madness.
page 495:
- The modern world, at present, seems to be moving towards a solution like that
of antiquity: a social order imposed by force, representing the will of the
powerful rather than the hopes of common men.
page 501:
-
The Renaissance was not a popular movement; it was a
movement of a small number of scholars and artists, encouraged by liberal
patrons, especially the Medici and the humanist popes.
-
“No man is more disgusted than I am with the ambition, the avarice, and the
profligacy of the priests, not only because each of these vices is hateful in
itself, but because each and all of them are most unbecoming in those who
declare themselves to be men in special relations with God, and also because
they are vices so opposed to one another, that they can only co-exist in very
singular natures. Nevertheless, my position at the
Court of several popes forced me to desire their greatness for the sake of my
own interest. But, had it not been for this, I should have loved Martin Luther
as myself, not in order to free myself from the laws which Christianity, as
generally understood and explained, lays upon us, but in order to see this
swarm of scoundrels put back into their proper place, so that they may be
forced to live either without vices or without power." -Guicciardini the
historian in 1529
page 502:
- The first effect of emancipation from the Church was not to make men think
rationally, but to open their minds to every sort of antique nonsense. [like astrology]
page 504:
- Savonarola dominated Florence; his miserable end evidently made a great
impression on Machiavelli, for he remarks that “all
armed prophets have conquered and unarmed ones failed," proceeding to
give Savonarola as an instance of the latter class.
page 505:
- his [Machiavelli’s] longer work, the Discourses, which he was writing at the same time, is
markedly more republican and more liberal. He says at the beginning of The Prince that he will not speak of republics in this
book, since he has dealt with them elsewhere. Those who do not read also the
Discourses are likely to get a very one-sided view of his doctrine.
page 508:
- chapter (XVIIII) [The Prince] entitled: “In What
Way Princes Must Keep Faith.” We learn that they should keep faith when it pays
to do so, but not otherwise. A prince must on occasion be faithless. “But it
is necessary to be able to disguise this character well, and to be a great
feigner and dissembler; and men are so simple and so ready to obey present
necessities, that one who deceives will always find those who allow themselves
to be deceived. I will mention only One modern instance. Alexander VI did
nothing else but deceive men, he thought of nothing else, and found the
occasion for it; no man was ever more able to give assurances, or affirmed
things with stronger oaths, and no man observed them less; however, he always
succeeded in his deceptions, as he knew well this aspect of things. It is not necessary therefore for a prince to have all the
above- named qualities [the conventional virtues], but it is very necessary to
seem to have them."
page 510:
- It is true that power, often, depends upon opinion,
and opinion upon propaganda; it is true, also, that it is an advantage
in propaganda to seem more virtuous than your adversary, and that one way of
seeming virtuous is to be virtuous.
page 518:
-
More is remembered almost solely on account of
his Utopia (1518). Utopia is an island in the
southern hemisphere, where everything is done in the best possible way.
-
Like Plato, communism, men and women all trained to
fight, no property, get other nations into their debt.
page 521:
- Raphael Hythloday [the protagonist of Utopia]
relates that he preached Christianity to the Utopians, and that many were
converted when they learnt that Christ was opposed to private property. The
importance of communism is constantly stressed; almost at the end we are told
that in all other nations “I can perceive nothing but a
certain conspiracy of rich men procuring their own commodities under the name
and title of the common wealth."
page 522:
- Diversity is essential to happiness, and in Utopia
there is hardly any. This is a defect of all planned social systems, actual as
well as imaginary.
page 523:
-
The three great men of the Reformation and Counter-Reformation are Luther, Calvin, and Loyola.
-
Luther and Calvin reverted to Saint Augustine, retaining, however, only that
part of his teaching which deals with the relation of the soul to God, not the
part which is concerned with the Church.
-
They rejected the doctrine of Indulgences, upon which a large part of the
papal revenue depended.
page 524:
- Protestant success, at first amazingly rapid, was checked mainly as a
resultant of Loyola’s creation of the Jesuit
order. Loyola had been a soldier, and his order was founded on military
models; there must be unquestioning obedience to the General, and every Jesuit
was to consider himself engaged in warfare against heresy. As early as the
Council of Trent, the Jesuits began to be influential. They were disciplined,
able, completely devoted to the cause, and skilful propagandists. Their
theology was the opposite of that of the Protestants; they rejected those
elements of Saint Augustine’s teaching which the Protestants emphasized. They believed in free will, and opposed predestination.
Salvation was not by faith alone, but by both faith and works.
- They concentrated on education, and thus acquired a
firm hold on the minds of the young. Whenever theology did not
interfere, the education they gave was the best obtainable; we shall see that
they taught Descartes more mathematics than he would have learnt elsewhere.
page 525:
- Disgust with theological warfare turned the attention of able men
increasingly to secular learning, especially mathematics and science.
page 525:
-
Descartes, who was in a sense the founder of modern philosophy, was himself
one of the creators of seventeenth century science.
-
Four great men–Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, and Newton–are pre-eminent in
the creation of science.
page 531:
- Galileo (1564-1642) is the greatest of the founders of modern science, with
the possible exception of Newton. He was born on about the day on which
Michelangelo died, and he died in the year in which Newton was born. I commend
these facts to those (if any) who still believe in metempsychosis.
page 536:
- In 1700 the mental outlook of educated men was completely modern; in 1600,
except among a very few, it was still largely medieval.
page 538:
-
To be humble before God was both right and prudent, for God would punish
pride. Pestilences, floods, earthquakes, Turks, Tartars, and comets perplexed the gloomy centuries,
and it was felt that only greater and greater humility would avert these real
or threatened calamities. But it became impossible to remain humble when men
were achieving such triumphs: Nature and Nature’s laws lay hid in night. God
said “Let Newton be,” and all was light
-
There were of course many other reasons for self-satisfaction. The Tartars had been confined to Asia, and the Turks
were ceasing to be a menace. Comets had been humbled by Halley, and as for
earthquakes, though they were still formidable, they were so interesting that
men of science could hardly regret them. Western
Europeans were growing rapidly richer, and were becoming lords of all the
world: they had conquered North and South America, they were powerful in
Africa and India, respected in China and feared in Japan. When to all this were
added the triumphs of science, it is no wonder that the men of the seventeenth
century felt themselves to be fine fellows, not the miserable sinners that they
still proclaimed themselves on Sundays.
page 542:
- Bacon was the first of the long line of scientifically minded philosophers
who have emphasized the importance of induction as opposed to deduction.
page 546:
- He proclaims, at the very beginning of the book, his thoroughgoing materialism. Life, he says, is nothing
but a motion of the limbs, and therefore automata have an artificial life. The
commonwealth, which he calls Leviathan, is a creation of art, and is in fact an
artificial man. This is intended as more than an analogy, and is worked out in
some detail. The sovereignty is an artificial soul.
page 547:
- Hobbes, as might be expected, is an out-and-out nominalist. There is, he
says, nothing universal but names, and without words we
could not conceive any general ideas. Without language, there would be no truth
or falsehood, for “true” and “false” are attributes of speech.
page 548:
- In a state of nature, there is no property, no justice or injustice; there is
only war, and “force and fraud are, in war, the two
cardinal virtues."
page 549:
-
Hobbes considers the question why men cannot co-operate like ants and bees.
Bees in the same hive, he says, do not compete; they have no desire for honour;
and they do not use reason to criticize the government. Their agreement is natural, but that of men can only be
artificial, by covenant. The covenant must confer power on one man or one
assembly, since otherwise it cannot be enforced. “Covenants, without the
sword, are but words." ( President Wilson unfortunately forgot this.)
The covenant is not, as afterwards in Locke and Rousseau, between the citizens
and the ruling power; it is a covenant made by the citizens with each other to
obey such ruling power as the majority shall choose. When they have chosen,
their political power is at an end. The minority is as much bound as the
majority, since the covenant was to obey the government chosen by the majority.
When the government has been chosen, the citizens lose
all rights except such as the government may find it expedient to grant. There
is no right of rebellion, because the ruler is not bound by any contract,
whereas the subjects are.
-
A multitude so united is called a commonwealth. This
“Leviathan” is a mortal God.
-
Hobbes prefers monarchy
-
The supreme power, whether a man or an assembly, is called the Sovereign.
The powers of the sovereign, in Hobbes’s system, are
unlimited. He has the right of censorship over all expression of
opinion. It is assumed that his main interest is the preservation of internal
peace, and that therefore he will not use the power of censorship to suppress
truth, for a doctrine repugnant to peace cannot be true. (A singularly
pragmatist view!) The laws of property are to be entirely subject to the
sovereign; for in a state of nature there is no
property, and therefore property is created by government, which may control
its creation as it pleases.
page 550:
- It is admitted that the sovereign may be despotic,
but even the worst despotism is better than anarchy. Moreover, in many points
the interests of the sovereign are identical with those of his subjects. He is
richer if they are richer, safer if they are law-abiding, and so on.
Rebellion is wrong, both because it usually fails, and because, if it succeeds,
it sets a bad example, and teaches others to rebel. The Aristotelian
distinction between tyranny and monarchy is rejected; a “tyranny,” according to
Hobbes, is merely a monarchy that the speaker happens to dislike.
page 551:
- All teachers are to be ministers of the sovereign,
and are to teach only what the sovereign thinks useful.
page 552:
- There should be days set apart for learning the duty of submission.
page 553:
- Every community is faced with two dangers, anarchy
and despotism. The Puritans, especially the Independents, were most
impressed by the danger of despotism. Hobbes, on the contrary, was obsessed by
the fear of anarchy.
page 555:
- usually considered the founder of modern philosophy,
page 556:
- Socrates used to meditate all day in the snow, but Descartes’s mind only
worked when he was warm.
page 557:
-
(he seldom got up before midday),
-
He lived in Holland for twenty years ( 1629-49), except for a few brief
visits to France and one to England, all on business. It is impossible to exaggerate the importance of Holland in
the seventeenth century, as the one country where there was freedom of
speculation. Hobbes had to have his books printed there; Locke took
refuge there during the five worst years of reaction in England before 1688;
Bayle (of the Dictionary) found it necessary to live there; and Spinoza would
hardly have been allowed to do his work in any other country.
page 558:
- He was not industrious; he worked short hours, and read little. … His work
seems to have been done with great concentration during short periods; but
perhaps, to keep up the appearance of a gentlemanly amateur, he may have
pretended to work less than in fact he did, for otherwise his achievements seem
scarcely credible.
page 559:
- He regarded the bodies of men and animals as
machines; animals he regarded as automata, governed entirely by the laws of
physics, and devoid of feeling or consciousness. Men are different: they have a
soul, which resides in the pineal gland. There the soul comes in contact
with the “vital spirits,” and through this contact there is interaction between
soul and body. The total quantity of motion in the universe is constant, and
therefore the soul cannot affect it; but it can alter the direction of motion
of the animal spirits, and hence, indirectly, of other parts of the body.
page 562:
- “I think, therefore I am” (cogito ergo sum), is known
as Descartes’s cogito, and the process by which it is reached is cared
“Cartesian doubt."
page 568:
- There can be only one Being who is wholly positive, and He must be absolutely
infinite. Hence Spinoza is led to a complete and undiluted pantheism.
page 569:
- Spinoza’s complete rejection of free will.
page 570:
- “The mind’s highest good is the knowledge of God, and the mind’s highest
virtue is to know God.” Emotions are called “passions” when they spring from
inadequate ideas; passions in different men may conflict, but men who live in obedience to reason will agree
together.
page 572:
- Spinoza does not, like the Stoics, object to all emotions; he objects only to
those that are “passions,” i.e., those in which we appear to ourselves to be
passive in the power of outside forces. “An emotion which is a passion ceases
to be a passion as soon as we form a clear and distinct idea of it.”
Understanding that all things are necessary helps the mind to acquire power
over the emotions. “He who clearly and distinctly
understands himself and his emotions, loves God, and so much the more as he
more understands himself and his emotions." This proposition introduces
us to the “intellectual love of God,” in which wisdom consists. The
intellectual love of God is a union of thought and emotion: it consists, I
think one may say, in true thought combined with joy in the apprehension of
truth.
page 573:
- Every increase in the understanding of what happens
to us consists in referring events to the idea of God, since, in truth,
everything is part of God. This understanding of everything as part of God is
love of God. When all objects are referred to God, the idea of God will fully
occupy the mind.
page 574:
- Blessedness, which consists of love towards God, is
not the reward of virtue, but virtue itself; we do not rejoice in it because we
control our lusts, but we control our lusts because we rejoice in it.
page 577:
- Such reflections may not suffice to constitute a religion, but in a painful
world they are a help towards sanity and an antidote to the paralysis of utter
despair.
page 578:
- It was the popular Leibniz who invented the doctrine that this is the best of
all possible worlds (to which F. H. Bradley added the sardonic comment “and
everything in it is a necessary evil”); it was this Leibniz whom Voltaire
caricatured as Doctor Pangloss. It would be unhistorical to ignore this
Leibniz, but the other is of far greater philosophical importance.
page 580:
- He believed, consequently, in an infinite number of substances, which he
called “monads.” Each of these would have some of the properties of a physical
point, but only when viewed abstractly; in fact, each monad is a soul.
page 588:
- Leibniz was a firm believer in the importance of logic, not only in its own
sphere, but as the basis of metaphysics. He did work on
mathematical logic which would have been enormously important if he had
published it; he would, in that case, have been the founder of mathematical
logic, which would have become known a century and a half sooner than it did in
fact. He abstained from publishing, because he kept on finding evidence that
Aristotle’s doctrine of the syllogism was wrong on some points; respect for
Aristotle made it impossible for him to believe this, so he mistakenly supposed
that the errors must be his own.
page 597:
- The first comprehensive statement of the liberal philosophy is to be found in
Locke
page 600:
- Since there was no constitutional way of getting rid of James, there must be
a revolution, but it must be quickly ended, so as to give no opportunity for
disruptive forces. The rights of Parliament must be secured once for all. The
king must go, but monarchy must be preserved; it should
be, however, not a monarchy of Divine Right, but one dependent upon legislative
sanction, and so upon Parliament. By a combination of aristocracy and big
business, all this was achieved in a moment, without the necessity of
firing a shot. Compromise and moderation had succeeded, after every form of
intransigeance had been tried and had failed. The new king, being Dutch,
brought with him the commercial and theological wisdom for which his country
was noted. The Bank of England was created; the
national debt was made into a secure investment, no longer liable to
repudiation at the caprice of the monarch.
page 606:
-
“For where is the man that has uncontestable evidence of the truth of all
that he holds, or of the falsehood of all he condemns; or can say, that he has
examined to the bottom all his own or other men’s opinions? The necessity of
believing without knowledge, nay, often upon very slight grounds, in this
fleeting state of action and blindness we are in, should make us more busy and
careful to inform ourselves than to restrain others. . . . There is reason to
think, that if men were better instructed themselves, they would be less
imposing on others.” -Essays Concerning Human Understanding Book 4, Ch 16
-
Locke may be regarded as the founder of empiricism, which is the doctrine
that all our knowledge (with the possible exception of logic and mathematics)
is derived from experience.
page 618:
-
The hereditary principle has almost vanished from
politics.
-
Hindsight shows this is not at all the case. Trudeau in
Canada, the Bush’s, the Clinton’s, etc. You have such an advantage by being
born to a leader that is essentially hereditary in nature. Further, considering
the influence of long dead people, through their organizations, still command,
it is not hard to see that the people of today are still competing against the
likes of the Rockefellers, the Carnegies, and like ilk.
page 619:
-
the great corporations in America, which have, or had
until Pearl Harbor, powers almost equal to those of the government.
-
Why did they lose it after Pearl Harbor? Answer: they
didn’t.
-
Political dynasties have disappeared, but economic
dynasties survive.
page 620:
- Throughout the Middle Ages, the law of nature was
held to condemn “usury,” i.e., lending money at interest. Church
property was almost entirely in land, and landowners have always been borrowers
rather than lenders. But when Protestantism arose, its
support–especially the support of Calvinism–came chiefly from the rich
middle class, who were lenders rather than borrowers. Accordingly first Calvin,
then other Protestants, and finally the Catholic Church, sanctioned “usury.”
page 621:
- As a rule, the man who first thinks of a new idea is
so much ahead of his time that every one thinks him silly, so that he
remains obscure and is soon forgotten. Then, gradually, the world becomes ready
for the idea, and the man who proclaims it at the fortunate moment gets all the
credit.
page 631:
- We are told first that every man has private property in the produce of his
own labour–or, at least, should have. In pre-industrial days this maxim was
not so unrealistic as it has since become. Urban production was mainly by
handicraftsmen who owned their tools and sold their produce. As for
agricultural production, it was held by the school to which Locke belonged that
peasant proprietorship would be the best system. He
states that a man may own as much land as he can till, but not more. He
seems blandly unaware that, in all the countries of Europe, the realization of
this programme would be hardly possible without a bloody revolution.
page 632:
- The labour theory of value–i.e., the doctrine that
the value of a product depends upon the labour expended upon it–which some
attribute to Karl Marx and others to Ricardo, is to be found in Locke, and was
suggested to him by a line of predecessors stretching back to Aquinas.
As Tawney says, summarizing scholastic doctrine: “The essence of the argument
was that payment may properly be demanded by the craftsmen who make the goods,
or by the merchants who transport them, for both labour in their vocation and
serve the common need. The unpardonable sin is that of
the speculator or middleman, who snatches private gain by the exploitation of
public necessities. The true descendant of the doctrines of Aquinas is
the labour theory of value. The last of the schoolmen was Karl Marx.”
page 633:
- The labour theory of value has usually been advocated from hostility to some
class regarded as predatory. The Schoolmen, in so far as they held it, did so
from opposition to usurers, who were mostly Jews. Ricardo held it in opposition
to landowners, Marx to capitalists. But Locke seems to have held it in a
vacuum, without hostility to any class. His only hostility is to monarchs, but
this is unconnected with his views on value.
page 637:
- A new international Social Contract is necessary
before we can enjoy the promised benefits of government. When once an
international government has been created, much of Locke’s political philosophy
will again become applicable, though not the part of it that deals with
private property.
page 637:
- The heirs of Locke are, first Berkeley and Hume; second, those of the French
philosophes who did not belong to the school of Rousseau; third, Bentham and
the philosophical Radicals; fourth, with important accretions from Continental
philosophy, Marx and his disciples.
page 643:
-
both in England and in America, big business on the
whole dislikes war.
-
WHAT?! The military industrial complex. War
profiteering. This is an outlandish statement. There is no excuse for this
nonsense, even in the day when it was written, circa WW2.
page 643:
- GORGE BERKELEY (1685-1753) is important in philosophy through his denial of
the existence of matter–a denial which he supported by a number of ingenious
arguments. He maintained that material objects only exist through being
perceived. To the objection that, in that case, a tree, for instance, would
cease to exist if no one was looking at it, he replied that God always
perceives everything; if there were no God, what we take to be material objects
would have a jerky life, suddenly leaping into being when we look at them; but
as it is, owing to God’s perceptions, trees and rocks and stones have an
existence as continuous as common sense supposes.
page 658:
- the “Self,” as defined, can be nothing but a bundle of perceptions, not a new
simple “thing.” In this I think that any thoroughgoing empiricist must agree
with Hume.
page 661:
-
Hume is thus led to the view that, when we say “A causes B,” we mean only
that A and B are constantly conjoined in fact, not that there is some necessary
connection between them. “We have no other notion of cause and effect, but that
of certain objects, which have been always conjoined together. . . . We cannot
penetrate into the reason of the conjunction.”
-
“Objects have no discoverable connexion together; nor is it from any other
principle but custom operating upon the imagination, that we can draw any
inference from the appearance of one to the experience of another.”
page 667:
- “…the truth of my hypothesis, that all our
reasonings concerning causes and effects are derived from nothing but custom;
and that belief is more properly an act of the sensitive, than of the
cogitative part of our natures."
page 669:
- To this extent, Hume has proved that pure empiricism
is not a sufficient basis for science. But if this one principle is admitted,
everything else can proceed in accordance with the theory that all our
knowledge is based on experience.
Part II. From Rousseau to the Present Day
page 670:
- But before we can understand its political and philosophical effects we must
consider it in its most essential form, which is as a revolt against received
ethical and aesthetic standards.
page 671:
- For long periods of his [Rousseau] life, he was a
poor vagabond, receiving kindness from people only slightly less destitute than
himself.
page 673:
- The romantics did not aim at peace and quiet, but at vigorous and passionate
individual life. They had no sympathy with industrialism, because it was ugly,
because money-grubbing seemed to them unworthy of an
immortal soul, and because the growth of modern economic organizations
interfered with individual liberty. In the post-revolutionary period they were
led into politics, gradually, through nationalism: each nation was felt to have
a corporate soul, which could not be free so long as the boundaries of States
were different from those of nations. In the first half of the nineteenth
century, nationalism was the most vigorous of revolutionary principles, and
most romantics ardently favoured it.
page 676:
- The mystic becomes one with God, and in the contemplation of the Infinite
feels himself absolved from duty to his neighbour. The anarchic rebel does even
better: he feels himself not one with God, but God. Truth and duty, which
represent our subjection to matter and to our neighbours, exist no longer for
the man who has become God; for others, truth is what he posits, duty what he
commands. If we could all live solitary and without
labour, we could all enjoy this ecstasy of independence; since we cannot, its
delights are only available to madmen and dictators.
- Revolt of solitary instincts against social bonds is
the key to the philosophy, the politics, and the sentiments, not only of what
is commonly called the romantic movement, but of its progeny down to the
present day.
page 678:
-
Belief in blood and race is naturally associated with anti-Semitism.
-
Naturally! Anyone who prefers their blood and race must
hate, not all other races, but only the Jews. Makes total sense…
-
“Who hold the balance of the world? Who reign O’er conquerors, whether
royalist or liberal? Who rouse the shirtless patriots of Spain? (That make old
Europe’s journals squeak and gibber all.) Who keep the world, both Old and New,
in pain Or pleasure? Who make politics run glibber all? The shade of
Buonaparte’s noble daring? Jew Rothschild, and his fellow Christian Baring.”
-Byron
-
The verse is perhaps not very musical, but the sentiment is quite of our
time, and has been re- echoed by all Byron’s followers.
-
Does he hate Jews or the Jews that attempt to ‘control
the world’? Is the charge levied inaccurate?
-
The romantic movement, in its essence, aimed at
liberating human personality from the fetters of social convention and social
morality.
-
Interesting that this is exactly what the (Jew
controlled) media is doing to this day.
page 684:
- When Voltaire tried to get the ban removed, Rousseau entered the lists on the
Puritan side. Savages never act plays; Plato disapproves of them; the Catholic Church refuses to marry or bury actors;
Bossuet calls the drama a “school of concupiscence.”
page 685:
- The Social Contract was even more dangerous, for it advocated democracy and
denied the divine right of kings. The two books, [Emile and
The Social Contract] while they greatly increased his fame, brought upon
him a storm of official condemnation. He was obliged to fly from France; Geneva
would have none of him * ; Bern refused him asylum. At last Frederick the Great
took pity on him, and allowed him to live at Motiers, near Neuchatel… [after 3 years the villagers accused him of poisoning and ran him
out of town. He went to live with Hume.
page 686:
- But in the end his delusions won [That Hume, whom he was
staying with was plotting against him] the day and he fled. His last
years were spent in Paris in great poverty, and when he died suicide was
suspected.
page 687:
- “I do not deduce these rules,” he says, “from the principles of a high
philosophy, but I find them in the depths of my heart, written by Nature in
ineffaceable characters.” -Rousseau in Emile
page 688:
- Our natural feelings, he contends, lead us to serve the common interest,
while our reason urges selfishness. We have therefore only to follow feeling
rather than reason in order to be virtuous.
page 689:
- The old arguments at least were honest: if valid,
they proved their point; if invalid, it was open to any critic to prove them
so. But the new theology of the heart dispenses with argument; it cannot be
refuted, because it does not profess to prove its points.
page 695:
- What we call democracy he calls elective aristocracy;
this, he says, is the best of all governments, but it is not suitable to all
countries.
- The Social Contract became the Bible of most of the
leaders in the French Revolution, but no doubt, as is the fate of
Bibles, it was not carefully read and was still less understood by many of its
disciples.
page 699:
- Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is generally considered the greatest of modern
philosophers. I cannot myself agree with this estimate, but it would be foolish
not to recognize his great importance.
page 701:
- Kant most important book is The Critique of Pure Reason. (1st edition 1781;
2nd edition 1787.) The purpose of this work is to prove that, although none of
our knowledge can transcend experience, it is nevertheless in part a priori and
not inferred inductively from experience.
page 703:
- The twelve categories are divided into four sets of three: (1) of quantity:
unity, plurality, totality; (2) of quality: reality, negation, limitation; (3)
of relation: substance-and-accident, cause-and- effect, reciprocity; (4) of
modality: possibility, existence, necessity.
page 705:
- Kant ethical system, as set forth in his Metaphysic of Morals (1785), has
considerable historical importance. This book contains the “categorical
imperative,”
page 706:
- Kant’s vigour and freshness of mind in old age are shown by his treatise on
Perpetual Peace (1795). In this work he advocates a federation of free States,
bound together by a covenant forbidding war. Reason, he
says, utterly condemns war, which only an international government can
prevent.
page 712:
-
Kant’s immediate successor, Fichte
(1762-1814), abandoned “things in themselves,” and carried subjectivism
to a point which seems almost to involve a kind of insanity. He holds that the
Ego is the only ultimate reality, and that it exists because it posits itself;
the non-Ego, which has a subordinate reality, also exists only because the Ego
posits it. Fichte is not important as a pure philosopher, but as the
theoretical founder of German nationalism, by his Addresses to the German Nation (1807-8), which were
intended to rouse the Germans to resistance to Napoleon after the battle of
Jena. The Ego as a metaphysical concept easily became confused with the
empirical Fichte; since the Ego was German, it followed that the Germans were
superior to all other nations. “To have character and to be a German,” says
Fichte, “undoubtedly mean the same thing.” On this basis he worked out a whole
philosophy of nationalistic totalitarianism, which had great influence in
Germany.
-
The important development from Kant’s philosophy was that of Hegel.
page 715:
- Men are born ignorant, not stupid; they are made
stupid by education.
page 716:
-
He [Condorcet] was a believer in the equality of
women. He was also the inventor of Malthus’s theory of
population, which, however, had not for him the gloomy consequences that it had
for Malthus, because he coupled it with the necessity of birth control.
Malthus’s father was a disciple of Condorcet, and it was in this way that
Malthus came to know of the theory.
-
This was in the mid to late 1700s.
page 717:
-
Men who were in revolt against tradition, as
already mentioned, were of two kinds, rationalistic and romantic…
-
The Benthamites were almost wholly rationalistic, and so were the Socialists
who rebelled against them as well as against the existing economic order. This
movement does not acquire a complete philosophy until we come to Marx,
page 719:
-
at what stage in evolution did men, or their semi- human ancestors, begin to
be all equal? Would Pithecanthropus erectus, if he had been properly educated,
have done work as good as Newton’s? Would the Piltdown
Man have written Shakespeare’s poetry if there had been anybody to
convict him of poaching? A resolute egalitarian who answers these questions in
the affirmative will find himself forced to regard apes as the equals of human
beings. And why stop with apes?
-
It is amazing how influential the hoax of the Piltdown
man had.
page 720:
- Marx himself, though his. doctrines are in some
respects pre- Darwinian, wished to dedicate his book to Darwin.
page 721:
- In old days, peasants lived as their parents and grandparents had lived, and
believed as their parents and grandparents had believed; not all the power of
the Church could eradicate pagan ceremonies, which had to be given a Christian
dress by being connected with local saints. Now the authorities can decree what
the children of peasants shall learn in school, and can transform the mentality
of agriculturists in a generation…
- first, the power of man in his conflicts with nature, and then the power of rulers as against the human beings whose beliefs
and aspirations they seek to control by scientific propaganda, especially
education. The result is a diminution of fixity; no change seems
impossible. Nature is raw material; so is that part of
the human race which does not effectively participate in government.
page 722:
- Marx, as every one knows, was a disciple of Hegel in his youth, and retained
in his own finished system some important Hegelian features.
page 726:
- Truth and falsehood are not sharply defined opposites, as is commonly
supposed; nothing is wholly false, and nothing that we can know is wholly true.
page 731:
- he says that, as yet, there is no real State in America, because a real State
requires a division of classes into rich and poor.
page 732:
-
We are told in The Philosophy of History that “the State is the actually
existing realized moral life,” and that all the spiritual reality possessed by
a human being he possesses only through the State. “For his spiritual reality
consists in this, that his own essence–Reason–is objectively present to him,
that it possesses objective immediate existence for him. . . . For truth is the
unity of the universal and subjective Will, and the universal is to be found in
the State, in its laws, its universal and rational arrangements. The State is the Divine Idea as its exists on earth."
Again: “The State is the embodiment of rational freedom, realizing and
recognizing itself in an objective form. . . . The
State is the Idea of Spirit in the external manifestation of human Will and its
Freedom."
-
The Philosophy of Law, in the section on the State, develops the same
doctrine somewhat more fully. “The State is the reality
of the moral idea–the moral spirit, as the visible substantial will, evident
to itself, which thinks and knows itself, and fulfils what it knows in so far
as it knows it." The State is the rational in and for itself. If the
State existed only for the interests of individuals (as Liberals contend), an
individual might or might not be a member of the State. It has, however, a
quite different relation to the individual: since it is objective Spirit, the
individual only has objectivity, truth, and morality in so far as he is a
member of the State, whose true content and purpose is union as such. It is
admitted that there may be bad States, but these merely exist, and have no true
reality, whereas a rational State is infinite in itself.
page 733:
- He goes on to argue against any sort of League of Nations by which the
independence of separate States might be limited.
- Hegel does not mean only that, in some situations, a nation cannot rightly
avoid going to war. He means much more than this. He is
opposed to the creation of institutions–such as a world government –which
would prevent such situations from arising, because he thinks it a good thing
that there should be wars from time to time. War, he says, is the
condition in which we take seriously the vanity of temporal goods and things.
(This view is to be contrasted with the opposite theory, that all wars have
economic causes.) War has a positive moral value: “War has the higher
significance that through it the moral health of peoples is preserved in their
indifference towards the stabilizing of finite determinations.” Peace is
ossification; the Holy Alliance, and Kant’s League for Peace, are mistaken,
because a family of States needs an enemy.
Conflicts of States can only be decided by war
page 734:
- Hegel’s logic led him to believe that there is more reality or excellence
(the two for him are synonyms) in wholes than in their parts, and that a whole
increases in reality and excellence as it becomes more organized. This justified him in preferring a State to an anarchic
collection of individuals, but it should equally have led him to prefer a world
State to an anarchic collection of States.
page 741:
- Byron, though he felt himself the equal of Satan, never quite ventured to put
himself in the place of God.
page 745:
- He dislikes Christianity, preferring the religions of India, both Hinduism
and Buddhism. He is a man of wide culture, quite as much interested in art as
in ethics. He is unusually free from nationalism
page 751:
- in proportion as will has gone up in the scale, knowledge has gone down. This
is, I think, the most notable change that has come over the temper of
philosophy in our age. It was prepared by Rousseau and Kant, but was first
proclaimed in its purity by Schopenhauer.
page 751:
-
NIETZSCHE (1844-1900) regarded himself, rightly, as the successor of
Schopenhauer, to whom, however, he is superior in many ways, particularly in
the consistency and coherence of his doctrine.
-
in Nietzsche, the will has ethical as well as metaphysical primacy.
page 754:
- “Everything that pampers, that softens, and that brings the ‘people’ or
‘woman’ to the front, operates in favour of universal suffrage–that is to say,
the dominion of ‘inferior’ men.” The seducer was Rousseau, who made woman
interesting; then came Harriet Beecher Stowe and the slaves; then the
Socialists with their championship of workmen and the poor. All these are to be
combated.
-
Nietzsche’s ethic is not one of self-indulgence in
any ordinary sense; he believes in Spartan discipline and the capacity to
endure as well as inflict pain for important ends. He admires strength of will
above all things. “I test the power of a will,” he says, “according to the
amount of resistance it can offer and the amount of pain and torture it can
endure and know how to turn to its own advantage; I do not point to the
evil and pain of existence with the finger of reproach, but rather entertain
the hope that life may one day become more evil and more full of suffering than
it has ever been.” He regards compassion as a weakness to be combated. “The
object is to attain that enormous energy of greatness which can model the man
of the future by means of discipline and also by means of the annihilation of
millions of the bungled and botched, and which can yet avoid going to ruin at
the sight of the suffering created thereby, the like of which has never been
seen before.”
-
He is not, however, a worshipper of the State; far from it. He is a
passionate individualist, a believer in the hero. The misery of a whole nation,
he says, is of less importance than the suffering of a great individual: “The
misfortunes of all these small folk do not together constitute a sum-total,
except in the feelings of mighty men.”
page 755:
- Nietzsche is not a nationalist, and shows no excessive admiration for
Germany. He wants an international ruling race, who are
to be the lords of the earth: “a new vast aristocracy based upon the most
severe self-discipline, in which the will of philosophical men of power and
artist-tyrants will be stamped upon thousands of years."
page 772:
-
Ricardo, who was intimately associated with Bentham, Malthus, and James Mill,
taught that the exchange value of a commodity is entirely due to the labour
expended in producing it. He published this theory in 1817, and eight years
later Thomas Hodgskin, an ex- naval officer, published the first Socialist
rejoinder, Labour Defended Against the Claims of Capital. He argued that if, as
Ricardo taught, all value is conferred by labour, then all the reward ought to
go to labour; the share at present obtained by the landowner and the capitalist
must be mere extortion. Meanwhile Robert Owen, after much practical experience
as a manufacturer, had become convinced of the doctrine which soon came to be
called Socialism. (The first use of the word “Socialist” occurs in 1827, when
it is applied to the followers of Owen.) Machinery, he said, was displacing
labour, and laisser faire gave the working classes no adequate means of
combating mechanical power. The method which he proposed for dealing with the
evil was the earliest form of modern Socialism.
-
In a later letter, James Mill attributes the doctrine to the “mad nonsense”
of Hodgskin, and adds: “These opinions, if they were to spread, would be the
subversion of civilized society; worse than the overwhelming deluge of Huns and
Tartars.”
page 775:
- “Philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways, but the real
task is to alter it.”
page 776:
- The politics, religion, philosophy, and art of any epoch in human history
are, according to Marx, an outcome of its methods of production, and, to a
lesser extent, of distribution.
page 779:
- Hegel thought of nations as the vehicles of dialectic movement; Marx
substituted classes.
page 813:
- Dewey makes inquiry the essence of logic, not truth
or knowledge. He defines inquiry as follows: “Inquiry is the controlled
or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is so
determinate in its constituent distinctions and relations as to convert the
elements of the original situation into a unified whole.” He adds that “inquiry
is concerned with objective transformations of objective subject-matter.” This
definition is plainly inadequate.
page 817:
- Dr. Dewey’s world, it seems to me, is one in which
human beings occupy the imagination…
page 818:
- The concept of “truth” as something dependent upon
facts largely outside human control has been one of the ways in which
philosophy hitherto has inculcated the necessary element of humility. When this
check upon pride is removed, a further step is taken on the road towards a
certain kind of madness–the intoxication of power which invaded
philosophy with Fichte, and to which modern men, whether philosophers or not,
are prone. I am persuaded that this intoxication is the greatest danger of our
time, and that any philosophy which, however unintentionally, contributes to it is increasing the danger of vast social
disaster.
page 823:
- Philosophy, throughout its history, has consisted of two parts inharmoniously
blended: on the one hand a theory as to the nature of the world, on the other
an ethical or political doctrine as to the best way of living. The failure to
separate these two with sufficient clarity has been a source of much confused
thinking.